by Neville Buch | Mar 2, 2024 | Concepts in Educationalist Thought Series, Concepts in Public History for Marketplace Dialogue, Letter
TO WHOM IT CONCERNS…who cares?
Thanks for the information on what is being discussed in the communities and the media.
Yes, we have two reasonable options here in policy: [below and to the ABC link] Free higher education for courses with large fieldwork programs. Or the industries of the industry partnerships in the fieldwork programs contribute significantly to the students’ personal income cost, at a reasonable rate for the work performed, with the university bearing the administration cost of the industry partnership on both ends, e.g. university school and hospital administration. As I understand it, the latter is being considered in some fashion, somewhere in government, but who really knows their philosophical intent and its translation into the practice of the sociology.
So there is some very creative thinking, just off the top of my head, and off the top of the head of 1,000s who are experts and have the same common sense and thinking. SO WHY is it that our federal and state bureaucracies cannot get their act together? If governments had the will to effectively change policies, they could. It would be too easy….with philosophic intelligence and intellectual historiography.
I get exhausted of sending our postings to these departments, pointing out the obvious (to us intellectuals), and I am not being paid and in financial strife.
We are all citizens in agreement on the common principle for the State and the Public sharing the economic weight in fairness. Unfortunately, most politicians have never had the opportunity for an education in a university classroom of philosophy to fully understand what the concept of fairness means according to Martha Nussbaum and Helena Rosenblaatt, rather than the narrow and populist reading of John Rawls.
Neil, I will write this letter up as an essay [this is the essay you are now reading] which will add a “Theory” section, and have it done by tonight.
Dr Donnell Davis might like to review it.
The critical point, though, is that it only takes me a day to write a high-level brief for a government and I am the one without an income, no paid job or contract, but do plenty of work, 6-8 hours 7 days a week.
I would like to know why?
THE REPLY SECTION OF THE LETTER
———- Forwarded message ———
From: Dr Donnell Davis <[email protected]>
Date: Sat, 2 Mar 2024 at 08:16
Subject: Education ? Placement poverty in Australia
To: Many Australian citizens
Dear colleagues,
It’s interesting that the countries with greatest advancements have free tertiary education, as we did from 1975 until education was commodified. What have we done so that 46% of high schoolers actually go to study for a trade or degree? The rest work in service industries, live on the dole, or are lucky to have a second chance eduction later in life.
I think we have the formulae wrong.
https://amp-abc-net-au.cdn.ampproject.org/c/s/amp.abc.net.au/article/103511408
And reform?
https://amp-abc-net-au.cdn.ampproject.org/c/s/amp.abc.net.au/article/103511408
Regards Donnell
D Australia
BIBLIOGRAPHY SECTION OF LETTER
Broome, J. (1984). Uncertainty and Fairness. The Economic Journal, 94(375), 624–632. https://doi.org/10.2307/2232707
Carr, C. L. (2002). Fairness and Political Obligation. Social Theory and Practice, 28(1), 1–28. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23559201
Hooker, B. (1995). Rule-Consequentialism, Incoherence, Fairness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95, 19–35. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4545206
Klosko, G. (1987). The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation. Ethics, 97(2), 353–362. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2381353
Klosko, G. (1993). Rawls’s “Political” Philosophy and American Democracy. The American Political Science Review, 87(2), 348–359. https://doi.org/10.2307/2939045
Neal, P. (1990). Justice as Fairness: Political or Metaphysical? Political Theory, 18(1), 24–50. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191478
Nussbaum, M. C. (1993). Equity and Mercy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 22(2), 83–125. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265442
Nussbaum, M. C. (2011). Perfectionist Liberalism and Political Liberalism. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39(1), 3–45. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41301860
Nussbaum, M.C. (2018). The Monarchy of Fear: a philosopher looks at our political crisis (First Edition). Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Rosenblatt, H. (2007). On the Intellectual Sources of Laïcité: Rousseau, Constant, and the Debates about a National Religion. French Politics, Culture & Society, 25(3), 1–18. http://www.jstor.org/stable/42843511
Rosenblatt, H. (2008). Rousseau, the Anticosmopolitan? Daedalus, 137(3), 59–67. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40543798
Rosenblatt, H. (2016). Rousseau, the “Traditionalist.” Journal of the History of Ideas, 77(4), 627–635. https://www.jstor.org/stable/jhistoryideas.77.4.627
Rosenblatt, H. (2016). On Context and Meaning in Pocock’s “Barbarism and Religion”, and on Gibbon’s “Protestantism” in His Chapters on Religion. Journal of the History of Ideas, 77(1), 147–155. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43948778
Rosenblatt, H. (2018). The Lost History of Liberalism: from ancient Rome to the twenty-first century. Princeton University Press, Princeton; Oxford.
Ryan, A. (2006). Fairness and Philosophy. Social Research, 73(2), 597–606. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40971838
Smith, C. R. (1999). The Campaign to Repeal the Fairness Doctrine. Rhetoric and Public Affairs, 2(3), 481–505. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41940183
Williams, B. (2000). Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline. Philosophy, 75(294), 477–496. http://www.jstor.org/stable/3751721
Duff, A., & von Hirsch, A. (1997). Responsibility, Retribution and the “Voluntary”: A Response to Williams. The Cambridge Law Journal, 56(1), 103–113. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4508303
And I am looking forward to the end of “The Great Australian Silence“…the conversation continues…
THEORY SECTION
What would it mean to be fair in higher education policy? To be able to answer this question the reader need to go to the philosophy literature to unpack the semantics of fairness. Using a research method of working the literature in chronological order, the following is a literature review on the topic and concept, of fairness:
Broome, J. (1984). Uncertainty and Fairness. The Economic Journal, 94(375), 624–632. https://doi.org/10.2307/2232707
Broome untangles the problem of consequentialism for understanding fairness: “I shall explain in a moment, that ‘social’ preferences do not obey the sure-thing principle, which is generally taken to be an essential requirement of rationality.” In doing so, and as my assessment, the critique of the sure-thing principle makes a nonsense of the (reductive) ‘unnecessary commitments’ claims for utilitarianism. The necessity of the calculation can be seen as perjurious from the defeat of the sure-thing principle for preferences; as preferences can never be completely true, and the otherwise-claimed testimony has sourced in some false information. Thus Broome has two-part argument on fairness:
- even granted that equalising people’s utilities is a way to be fair, that is no reason to think equalising expected utilities is.
- even granted the fairness of random selection on appropriate occasions, this fairness is not captured by valuing equality in expected utilities.
The issue here is the negativity, we don’t know what we don’t know. Only very tight contextual descriptions might provide an adequate basis for a political “calculation”. In time, though, most political calculations are shown to have missteps. Constant reviews of logical steps combined with the acceptance/room for fallible human action will provided the very tight contextual descriptions that would provide an adequate basis for a political judgement, not a numeric calculation. Here fairness can be achieved as a parameter.
Klosko, G. (1987). The Principle of Fairness and Political Obligation. Ethics, 97(2), 353–362. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2381353
Klosko helpfully unpacked the ethics of John Rawls and H. L. A. Hart. He shows that the obligations of the fairness principle generates widespread
and familiar attitudes toward political obligation, but its formulation as ethics is problematic. Bernard Williams resolved the issue in the distinction between moral obligation and ordinary, or political, obligation. The former is a problematic ethical formulation, the latter is normative.
Neal, P. (1990). Justice as Fairness: Political or Metaphysical? Political Theory, 18(1), 24–50. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191478
Neal brings out the wider historiographical and political philosophy issue, an almost impossible binary between the Political and the Metaphysics, which in most applied situations is false. This is why the populist reading of Rawls is almost always false:
It is not uncommon these days to hear John Rawls’s post-A Theory of Justice writings referred to with sentiments of regret, even disappointment. As has often been remarked, A Theory of Justice had an impact on the Anglo-Saxon intellectual world far beyond that achieved by most academic books. One (certainly not the only) reason for this was a widespread perception that Rawls was therein attempting a project of heroic proportion and classical scope: articulating a comprehensive and universal theory of justice founded on first principles. It is impossible to understand the praise bestowed on Rawls by friend and foe alike for “reviving” the practice of normative political theory without taking into account this perception. Of course, such praise was usually the prelude to a not so faint damnation, as critic after critic pointed to the gaps, holes and presuppositions in the (apparently not so) architectonic structure of Rawls’s theory, which I shall follow him in referring to as “justice as fairness” (JAF).
The general conclusion from Neal is that Rawls’ approach can work in political discourse but only with further structural work in the JAF concept, which goes beyond the normative use/abuse of the fairness concept.
Klosko, G. (1993). Rawls’s “Political” Philosophy and American Democracy. The American Political Science Review, 87(2), 348–359. https://doi.org/10.2307/2939045
By early 1990s Klosko took on Rawls head-on: “I criticize both Rawls’s general claims about the role of political philosophy and his particular defense of the principles of justice.” Rawls’ general claims is an argument around well-known principles of justice which can serve in a capacity for an overlapping consensus. Klosko is pointing to a rather different overlapping consensus that appears to contribute to stable democracies, a larger moral framing than the utilitarianism of Rawls. Fairness, in many technical senses, is at the heart of this wider project.
Nussbaum, M. C. (1993). Equity and Mercy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 22(2), 83–125. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2265442
Martha Nussbausm discussed in a completely different and much more hostile context than most in the law and public affairs, where it is normative to expect leniency:
By this time, the original and real etymology of the word epieikeia-from eikos, the “plausible” or “appropriate,” — is being supplemented by a popular derivation of the term from eiko, “yield,” “give way.” Thus even in writing the history of the term, Greek thinkers discover a connection between appropriate judgment and leniency.
The emphasis here is on connections not understood.
The puzzle lies, as I have said, in the unexplained connection between appropriate situational judgment and mercy. One might well suppose that a judgment that gets all the situational particulars correct will set the level of fault sometimes high up, sometimes low down, as the situation demands. If the judgment is a penalty-setting judgment, it will sometimes set a heavy penalty and sometimes a light one, again as the situation demands. If the equitable judgment or penalty are being contrasted with a general principle designed beforehand to fit a large number of situations — as is usually the case-then we might expect that the equitable will sometimes be more lenient than the generality of the law, but sometimes harsher.
This is one conception of fairness.
Hooker, B. (1995). Rule-Consequentialism, Incoherence, Fairness. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 95, 19–35. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4545206
Hooker argues that the normative understanding of fairness gives us no reason for thinking a maturely-developed Rule-Consequentialism is inferior to Contractualism. This is a technical argument over ethical theories. The point here is a debate over the fairness doctrine where the public has grossly misread the technical arguments.
Smith, C. R. (1999). The Campaign to Repeal the Fairness Doctrine. Rhetoric and Public Affairs, 2(3), 481–505. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41940183
In the United States during the 1980s Smith applied an ideological approach to communication strategies in a “Campaign to Repeal the Fairness Doctrine” for government funding and public policy:
Senator Packwood and I established a foundation which would coordinate the repeal effort using non-public funds and which could provide lobbyist, editorialists, and other opinion leaders with needed arguments and evidence. In December of 1982, the Freedom of Expression Foundation was established in Washington, D.C., using contributions from the major networks, AT&T, Washington Post Company, and Times-Mirror Company.
As president of the Foundation, I had a clear view of the campaign to repeal the Fairness Doctrine and saw that such efforts are easily caught up in the crosscurrents of ideology and partisan politics. From this perspective, I provide an inside look at public policy reform while revealing the role public address plays in a bureaucratic republic where there are multiple forums for persuasion.
The same communication strategies were applied in the Australian governmental bureaucracies, meaning too few can today have a fuller understanding of fairness.
Carr, C. L. (2002). Fairness and Political Obligation. Social Theory and Practice, 28(1), 1–28. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23559201
By the turn of the century the law was forced to catch up in the conceptual problem of fairness. Carr explains that unfortunately a false binary was created in public opinion in the choice of one school of theory:
Some philosophers think the demands of fairness will support an obligation to obey the law in what I will call reasonably decent polities. Of these, some hold the strong thesis that all persons who happen to reside within a reasonably decent polity are obligated upon pain of unfairness to obey the law regardless of whether they are, or consider themselves to be, citizens of the polity. Others hold the weaker thesis that only citizens are obligated to obey the law by the concerns of fairness. The difference, which spins upon the notion of membership in the polity, will likely seem cloudy at this point but should become more apparent momentarily. It should also become apparent that the distinction is a matter of some theoretical importance.
Carr takes a third theoretical position: “…I think fairness concerns give rise to an obligation, holding against acknowledged citizens only, to consider whether they should or should not obey the laws of their polity provided they are confident that their polity qualifies as reasonably decent.”
Ryan, A. (2006). Fairness and Philosophy. Social Research, 73(2), 597–606. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40971838
Ryan provided the history lesson on the concept of fairness, going back to David Hume. It is the necessary history lesson which, up to now, the political class has failed to understand, but it is a flawed lesson. From Hume, one school of philosophers see normative acts of praising and blaming as expressive and not descriptive. Hart developed this school of thought significantly, seeing ethics as non-obligatory, replaced by the obligation of the law. In this Bernard Williams followed Hart, but broke at certain stage of thinking on moral responsibility. Antony Duff and Andrew von Hirsch (1997) best explains it:
…Williams asserts, we should follow H.L.A. Hart in founding the argument for moral responsibility on the value of political freedom: if citizens “should be able to conduct their affairs so far as possible without the state’s power being unpredictably directed against them”, then punishments “should be applied to [and only to] voluntary agents”. We also should not expect too much, Williams asserts, from concept of the voluntary, since it is “both vague and superficial” The concept’s scope, that is, is indeterminate – we cannot always say whether an agent acted voluntarily, not because we cannot determine the truth of the matter, but because there is no “truth” of to be determined. And the concept cannot give us the kind of deep, or metaphysical, idea of “real” freedom of the will for which many (too many) still hanker. The upshot is that we should accept the conception of moral responsibility for what it is: a conception that is useful in certain contexts, but which does not reflect any profound truth about human agents or about how they should be treated.
In the philosophy of language Williams followed Wittgenstein on the conditions of linguistic uncertainty. This goes beyond Humean expressivism and Hart’s legal ethics. The way we normatively express a moral or an ethic is always uncertain in the language of morality and the law. The point for this essay is that such obligations cannot establish fairness as a general ethical principle. Fairness ought not be conflated with obligation. The two concepts might be contextual related, but that needs sufficient explanation.
Rosenblatt, H. (2007). On the Intellectual Sources of Laïcité: Rousseau, Constant, and the Debates about a National Religion. French Politics, Culture & Society, 25(3), 1–18. http://www.jstor.org/stable/42843511
Helena Rosenblatt is the intellectual historian who has unpacked the history of liberalism for its virtues, flaws, and missing elements in practice. She has done extraordinary work in dissecting the key thinkers of liberalism and missteps in thinking for national religion. Fairness is often (but not always) tied to religious beliefs.
Rosenblatt, H. (2008). Rousseau, the Anticosmopolitan? Daedalus, 137(3), 59–67. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40543798
One of Rosenblatt’s major contributions is to draw out missteps in the futile debate between the natural-birth and cosmopolitan visioning of nationalism. Behind the public ‘fairness’ discourses are these misconceptions.
Nussbaum, M. C. (2011). Perfectionist Liberalism and Political Liberalism. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39(1), 3–45. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41301860
Martha Nussbaum opens up an explanation of the different schools of liberalism in the late 20th century. Nussbaum declared her subscription to the school of “Political Liberalism” which has its leadership in Rawls and Charles Larmore. The approach is structurally singular, compared to and in opposition to — according to Nussbaum’s argument — Isaiah Berlin’s and Joseph Raz’s “Perfectionalist Liberalism”. This latter school of thought is also a “Moral Pluralist” and “Autonomous” Liberalism, with Raz emphasizing pluralistic valuing and personal (autonomous) action. In my work I do not think that Nussbaum has described the positioning of Berlin and Raz well. Berlin was not as perfectionist in his doctrine of liberalism (drawing on Kant’s “crooked timber”), and Raz’s conception of valuing does give a singular framework to an otherwise pluralistic landscape. All of these conceptions mentioned shaped the public perception of “fairness”, and, again, popularist misunderstandings abound from matters of technical debates.
Rosenblatt, H. (2016). Rousseau, the “Traditionalist.” Journal of the History of Ideas, 77(4), 627–635. https://www.jstor.org/stable/jhistoryideas.77.4.627
These technical debates have unfortunately extended into other futile ‘separation-type’ debates: Enlightenment versus Counter-Enlightenment; Tradition versus Natural Science.
Rosenblatt, H. (2016). On Context and Meaning in Pocock’s “Barbarism and Religion”, and on Gibbon’s “Protestantism” in His Chapters on Religion. Journal of the History of Ideas, 77(1), 147–155. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43948778
These futile ‘separation-type’ debates are known to intellectual historians as making a mess in the tangled world of religion and secularity, particularly for the Protestant tradition, which I have spent a lifetime unpacking.
Rosenblatt, H. (2018). The Lost History of Liberalism: from ancient Rome to the twenty-first century. Princeton University Press, Princeton; Oxford.
Rosenblatt’s book goes to what is missing in the public practice of liberty and fairness.
Nussbaum, M.C. (2018). The Monarchy of Fear: a philosopher looks at our political crisis (First Edition). Oxford University Press, Oxford.
Nussbaum’s book goes to the future, the severe risks to both democracy and fairness in the United States from Trumpism.
*****
It is hope that this theoretical “briefing” and letter will greatly assist government politicians and the bureaucrats in the fuller understanding of fairness, and that understanding will lead to practice.
—
Kind regards,
Neville Buch
Historian,
Professional Historians Australia (Queensland)
Australian and New Zealand History of Education Society (ANZHES)
Convenor, Sociology of Education Thematic Group, The Australian Sociological Association (TASA).
President, Southern Brisbane Suburban Forum (SBSF).
Director, Brisbane Southside History Network (BSHN).
MPHA (Qld), Ph.D. (History) UQ., Grad. Dip. Arts (Philosophy) Melb., Grad. Dip. (Education) UQ.
Call: 0416 046 429
ABN: 86703686642
by Neville Buch | Sep 1, 2023 | Concepts in Educationalist Thought Series, Concepts in Public History for Marketplace Dialogue
My response to the LinkedIn campaign, “How do you combine research and teaching in higher education?”, “Powered by AI and the LinkedIn community”.
I combine research and teaching in higher education by being personal. And it seems as if that is difficult for many to understand, but understood by billions of persons who have had enough of the game-playing. In many ways populism can be misguided but the personalism is not, and resistance to the personal is a political game to endeavour preventing the challenge to the game itself. The personal has an important place in professional life. It is also central to higher education, and also professional history.
I have already experienced backlash in my industry of professional history for my research and expression of personalism. I received a high-level complaint that I “[‘you’] appear to use it [social media] as a personal platform to vent about issues that concern you”. Nevertheless, I had feedback from historians, sociologists, and geographers, well under-employed who support me in bringing the painful, personable, experience to endure in the research of professional life. Furthermore, I have no complaints from the Australian Historical Association, where academics also truly know the personal cost of the game.
Featured Image: Range Of Personal Semantics
Range Of Personal Semantics
Bibliography
Abel, C. (2014). The extended self: Architecture, memes and minds. Manchester; New York: Manchester University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt1mf717q
Allen, Judith (1987) ‘Mundane’ men: Historians, masculinity and masculinism, Historical Studies, 22:89, 617-628, DOI: 10.1080/10314618708595772
Atkinson, Alan (2018) The I in the past, History Australia, 15:3, 578-590, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2018.1485466
Attwood, Bain (1990) Aborigines and academic historians: Some recent encounters, Australian Historical Studies, 24:94, 123-135, DOI: 10.1080/10314619008595835
Baker, L., et al (2001). Soul, Body, and Survival: Essays on the Metaphysics of Human Persons (Corcoran K., Ed.). Ithaca; London: Cornell University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.7591/j.ctv3s8s32
Bakker, J. (2011). The ‘Semiotic Self’: From Peirce and Mead to Wiley and Singer. The American Sociologist, 42(2/3), 187-206. Retrieved April 29, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/41485707
Bengtsson, Jan Olof (2006). The Worldview of Personalism : Origins and Early Development, Oxford University Press
Bertocci, P. (1954). The Nature of Cognition: Minimum Requirements for a Personalistic Epistemology. The Review of Metaphysics, 8(1), 49-60. Retrieved May 7, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/20123421
Bongiorno, Frank (2020) Geoffrey Blainey: Writer, Historian, Controversialist, Australian Historical Studies, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2020.1746997
Buch, Neville (2018). Small is Big: Scaling the Map for Brisbane Persons and Institutions 1825-2000. ‘The Scale of History’ AHA Conference, Australian National University, 4 July 2018.
Campbell, R. (1968). Personality as an Element of Regional Geography. Annals of the Association of American Geographers, 58(4), 748-759. Retrieved May 1, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/2561716
Carment, David (2018) Historians’ autobiographies and biographies, History Australia, 15:2, 381-383, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2018.1469191
Clarke, W. Norris (1994). The “We Are” of Interpersonal Dialogue as the Starting Point of Metaphysics (pp. 31-44), in Clarke, W. Explorations in Metaphysics: Being-God-Person. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. Retrieved May 7, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctvpj74zd
Curthoys, Ann (2019). Michelle Arrow on how the personal became political, History Australia, 16:3, 594-595, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2019.1636680
Evans, Tanya & Robert Reynolds (2012) Introduction to this Special Issue on Biography and Life-Writing, Australian Historical Studies, 43:1, 1-8, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2012.652301
Evans, Richard (2008) Review of Who Do You Think You Are?, History Australia, 5:3, 82.1-82.2, DOI: 10.2104/ha080082
Fraser, J. (1971). Personal and Political Meaning Correlates of Political Cynicism. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(2), 347–364. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110275
Frow, John (2014). Character & Person, Oxford University Press
Funnell, W. (2004). Accounting And The Pursuit Of Utopia: The Possibility Of Perfection In Paraguay. The Accounting Historians Journal, 31(1), 57-91. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/40698293
Gabay, Al (1987) The private writings of Alfred Deakin, Historical Studies, 22:89, 525-546, DOI: 10.1080/10314618708595767
Gasking, D. (1950) The historian’s craft and scientific history, Historical Studies: Australia and New Zealand, 4:14, 112-124, DOI: 10.1080/10314615008594886
Gilbert, Bennett (2020). A Personalist Philosophy of History, Routledge
Giovanni, B. Sala and Spoerl, J (1994). Intentionality versus Intuition (pp. 81-101) in Doran R. (Ed.), Lonergan and Kant (pp. 81-101). University of Toronto Press. Retrieved May 7, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.3138/j.ctt2tv28t.8
Hasker, W. (1999). The Emergent Self. Ithaca; London: Cornell University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.7591/j.ctvkjb3fx
Hilliard, Christopher (2017) Book Review: The Art of Time Travel: Historians and Their Craft, Australian Historical Studies, 48:3, 449-450, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2017.1337489
Huck, Arthur (1960) The Australian dictionary of biography, Historical Studies: Australia and New Zealand, 9:35, 313-314, DOI: 10.1080/10314616008595180
Hunt, H. (1995). Cognition and Consciousness. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 26-48). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.7
Hunt, H. (1995). Consciousness as Emergent: The Irrelevance of Specific Neurophysiology. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 51-72). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.9
Hunt, H. (1995). Consciousness as Society. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 279-296). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.22
Hunt, H. (1995). Consciousness as Space: Physics, Consciousness, and the Primacy of Perception. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 257-276). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.21
Hunt, H. (1995). Consciousness as Time. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 241-256). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.20
Hunt, H. (1995). Sensus Communis: A History of the Cross-Modal Theory of Mind. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 179-196). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.16
Hunt, H. (1995). The Most Fundamental of Empirical Questions or the Most Misguided—What Is Consciousness? In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 3-25). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.6
Hunt, H. (1995). William James and the Stream of Consciousness: Metaphor Without, Mirror Within. In On the Nature of Consciousness: Cognitive, Phenomenological, and Transpersonal Perspectives (pp. 115-138). Yale University Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/j.ctt32btm9.13
Hutch, R. (1980). The Personal Ritual of Glossolalia. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 19(3), 255-266. doi:10.2307/1385863
Kass, Terry and Carol Liston (1991) The professional historians association, Australian Historical Studies, 24:96, 217-221, DOI: 10.1080/10314619108595884
Kent, David (2015) ‘Sack the bastard!’ — ‘David Kent, (the now vilest man alive)’, History Australia, 12:1, 226-232, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2015.11668561
Kimball, E., Schnee, E., & Schwabe, L. (2015). Writing the Personal in an Outcomes-Based World. Composition Studies, 43(2), 113–131. http://www.jstor.org/stable/45157102
Lambek, Michael (2021). Concepts and Persons, University of Toronto Press
Lamiell, James T. (2021). Uncovering Critical Personalism : Readings from William Stern’s Contributions to Scientific Psychology, Springer Nature Switzerland AG
Loughnan, H. (1936). Emergence and The Self. The Monist,46(2), 211-227. Retrieved May 7, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/27901482
Martin, A.W. (1974) Henry Parkes: In search of the ‘actual man underneath’, Historical Studies, 16:63, 216-234, DOI: 10.1080/10314617408682886
Mayer, J. (1998). A Systems Framework for the Field of Personality. Psychological Inquiry, 9(2), 118-144. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/1449106
Mazzone, Derek (2017; 2020). The Pursuit of Value: A Philosophy of Loss and Equanimity, Sea Press, Singapore, SG.
McEwen, Ellen (1988) Australians 1888: A very personal view, Australian Historical Studies, 23:91, 114-120, DOI: 10.1080/10314618808595795
McLachlan, N. D. (1978) Australia to 1890: The dictionary of biography, Historical Studies, 18:71, 338-344, DOI: 10.1080/10314617808595596
McLennan Catherine and Liza Dale-Hallett (2008) Living History: An Agent for Change, History Australia, 5:3, 80.1, DOI: 10.2104/ha080080
Merrington, Earnest Northcoft (1916). The Problem of Personality: A Critical and Constructive Study in the Light of Recent Thought, London: Macmillan and Co. Limited.
Morito, B. (1989). Fundamental Ontology and Personal Identity: A Critique of Albert Shalom’s View of Personhood. The Review of Metaphysics, 42(4), 797-815. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/20128802
Munro, Doug (2012) Biographies of Historians – or, The Cliographer’s Craft, Australian Historical Studies, 43:1, 11-27, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2011.640694
O’Connor, Tamsin (2016) Who do we think we are? The perils of writing family history as national history, History Australia, 13:3, 453-455, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2016.1203389
Palmer, Sheridan (2012) The Importance of Leitmotifs and Distance in the Biography of Bernard Smith, Australian Historical Studies, 43:1, 28-44, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2011.647825
Popkin, Jeremy D. (2007) Ego‐histoire down under: Australian historian‐autobiographers, Australian Historical Studies, 38:129, 106-123, DOI: 10.1080/10314610708601234
Portus, G. V. (1940) H. A. L. Fisher: Historian—Statesman—Teacher, Historical Studies: Australia and New Zealand, 1:2, 122-124, DOI: 10.1080/10314614008594789
Poynter, J. R. (1971). R. M. Crawford: A bibliography, Historical Studies, 15:57, 22-26, DOI: 10.1080/10314617108595454
Quartly, Marian (2013) My life in history, History Australia, 10:3, 252-263, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2013.11668490
Read, Peter (2002) Clio or Janus? Historians and the stolen generations, Australian Historical Studies, 33:118, 54-60, DOI: 10.1080/10314610208596179
Rees, Anne (2018) Book Review: A Historian for All Seasons: Essays for Geoffrey Bolton, Australian Historical Studies, 49:2, 263-264, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2018.1454280
Rickard, John (1981) Parkes and Whitlam: The search for the ‘actual man underneath’, Historical Studies, 19:77, 602-606, DOI: 10.1080/10314618108595662
Sartre, Jean-Paul (1943, 2018). Being and Nothingness, Washington Square Press, New York, NY.
Saunders, Kay and Tom Stannage, and Richard Nile (1998). Paul Hasluck in Australian History: Civic Personality and Public Life. University of Queensland Press, St Lucia, Qld
Schwartz, S., Caprara, G., Vecchione, M., Bain, P., Bianchi, G., Caprara, M., . . . Zaleski, Z. (2014). Basic Personal Values Underlie and Give Coherence to Political Values: A Cross National Study in 15 Countries. Political Behavior, 36(4), 899-930. Retrieved April 29, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/43653359
Shoaps, R. (2002). “Pray Earnestly”: The Textual Construction of Personal Involvement in Pentecostal Prayer and Song. Journal of Linguistic Anthropology, 12(1), 34-71. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/43103994
Shoaps, Robin (2002). “Pray Earnestly”: The Textual Construction of Personal Involvement in Pentecostal Prayer and Song, Journal of Linguistic Anthropology, 12(1), 34-71. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/43103994
Stretton, Hugh (1981) The Botany Bay project: Historians and the study of cities, Historical Studies, 19:76, 430-439, DOI: 10.1080/10314618108595648
Sullivan, J., & Allen, S. (1981). An Odd Lot? Self-Help, Women, and War. Labour History, (41), 118-131. doi:10.2307/27508495
Turkle, S. (1997). Computational Technologies and Images of the Self. Social Research, 64(3), 1093-1111. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/40971200
Voget, F. (1960). Man and Culture: An Essay in Changing Anthropological Interpretation. American Anthropologist, 62(6), new series, 943-965. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/667593
Wilcox, Craig (2010) Pardon Me for Being an Historian, Australian Historical Studies, 41:2, 233-240, DOI: 10.1080/10314611003636564
Young, J. D. (1969) South Australian historians and Wakefield’s ‘scheme’, Historical Studies, 14:53, 32-53, DOI: 10.1080/10314616908595406
by Neville Buch | Jul 1, 2024 | Concepts in Public History for Marketplace Dialogue, Concepts in Religious Thought Series
“SOFiA is a network of Australians interested in openly exploring issues of life and meaning through reason, philosophy, ethics, religion, science and the arts. We want to explore for ourselves what we can believe and how we can find meaning in our lives.”
“SOFiA has no philosophical or religious position beyond a desire to ‘openly explore’: it is a forum for discussing ideas, experiences and possibilities.”
“Any who find themselves in sympathy with our purpose – exploring life and meaning in an open and non-dogmatic manner – are most welcome to join us.”
SOFiA website
This draft SoFiA position statement does not seek to change the IDEAL of the above statement, the ideal, though, it does not reflect our current reality. Exploring life and meaning in an open and non-dogmatic manner means accepting the philosophical reality. The ideal can be retained but a position statement should not be vague about how reality is shaping the thinking within the SoFiA organisation. There is no conflict between the SoFiA’s ideal and the fact that the organisation will advance its thinking in diverse ways.
What is the current philosophical reality in SoFiA?
In the last decade there has merged three positionings of thinking, not merely within SoFiA but also in the world that examines “issues of life and meaning through reason, philosophy, ethics, religion, science and the arts.”
NONES: declared no religious or organisational affiliation;
DONES: declared no institutional or formal affiliation;
MAINS: where there is declared affiliation, opposite of “nones” and “dones” and this is the traditional and mainstream outlook (a horizon worldview), and in the “main”, which has not caught up in the “historical delay.”
Lets be clear and frank. All three positions within SoFiA are legitimate, valid in reasoning, and are most welcomed with the SoFiA organisation.
The literature (see references below) has been developing on these three positions, and the point is that, in all three positions, within the positional thinking, the “issues of life and meaning through reason, philosophy, ethics, religion, science and the arts” are all contested. This does not mean that there is no actual positional thinking. The “Nones” most certainly have given up on religious or organisational affiliation. The statistics declare that the “Nones” as the fastest and largest growing grouping in belief systems for intellectually western nations. However, the statistics are most vague what the “Nones” means in terms of positive affirmations. The “Dones” are likely wise not easy to discern and there is some overlap with “Nones.” The difference with “Dones” is the no institutional or formal affiliation which means more than not having religious or organisational affiliation. It is a complete rejection of organised belief.
In reality, that is, in the unthinking ‘congregations’ of society, many of the “Mains” can also be hidden “Nones” or “Dones” and are persons only playing a game of convention. However, there are genuine intellectual “mains” who honestly declared their particular affiliation. They are also welcomed into the SoFiA family. Tradition evolves which means that the ideal and shifting reality can co-exist.
REFERENCES
Allen, I., & Allen, S. (2016). God Terms and Activity Systems: A Definition of Religion for Political Science. Political Research Quarterly, 69(3), 557–570. http://www.jstor.org/stable/44018555
Ammerman, N. T. (2013). Spiritual But Not Religious? Beyond Binary Choices in the Study of Religion. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 52(2), 258–278. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24644008
Baker, J. O., & Smith, B. G. (2009). The Nones: Social Characteristics of the Religiously Unaffiliated. Social Forces, 87(3), 1251–1263. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40345160
Baurain, B. (2011). Common Ground With A Common Faith: Dewey’s Idea of the “Religious.” Education and Culture, 27(2), 74–91. https://www.jstor.org/stable/10.5703/educationculture.27.2.74
Boutyline, A., & Vaisey, S. (2017). Belief Network Analysis: A Relational Approach to Understanding the Structure of Attitudes. American Journal of Sociology, 122(5), 1371–1447. https://www.jstor.org/stable/26545920
Burge, R. P. (2020). How Many “Nones” Are There? Explaining the Discrepancies in Survey Estimates. Review of Religious Research, 62(1), 173–190. http://www.jstor.org/stable/45286731
Condran, J. G., & Tamney, J. B. (1985). Religious “Nones”: 1957 to 1982. Sociological Analysis, 46(4), 415–423. https://doi.org/10.2307/3711157
Djupe, P. A., Neiheisel, J. R., & Conger, K. H. (2018). Are the Politics of the Christian Right Linked to State Rates of the Nonreligious? The Importance of Salient Controversy. Political Research Quarterly, 71(4), 910–922. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26600637
Duncan, A. W. (2017). Sacred Pregnancy in the Age of the “Nones.” Journal of the American Academy of Religion, 85(4), 1089–1115. https://www.jstor.org/stable/48556268
Edgell, P., Hartmann, D., Stewart, E., & Gerteis, J. (2016). Atheists and Other Cultural Outsiders: Moral Boundaries and the Non-Religious in the United States. Social Forces, 95(2), 607–638. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26166844
García, A., & Blankholm, J. (2016). The Social Context of Organized Nonbelief: County-Level Predictors of Nonbeliever Organizations in the United States. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 55(1), 70–90. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26651414
Glendinning, Tony. (2006). Religious Involvement, Conventional Christian, and Unconventional Nonmaterialist Beliefs. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 45(4), 585–595. http://www.jstor.org/stable/4621937
Goldstein, Michael. “Adjusting Belief Structures.” Journal of the Royal Statistical Society. Series B (Methodological) 50, no. 1 (1988): 133–54. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2345816.
Greer, B. A., & Roof, W. C. (1992). “Desperately Seeking Sheila”: Locating Religious Privatism in American Society. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 31(3), 346–352. https://doi.org/10.2307/1387125
Hadaway, C. K., & Roof, W. C. (1979). Those Who Stay Religious “Nones” and Those Who Don’t: A Research Note. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 18(2), 194–200. https://doi.org/10.2307/1385940
Hilbert, R. A. (1987). Bureaucracy as Belief, Rationalization as Repair: Max Weber in a Post-Functionalist Age. Sociological Theory, 5(1), 70–86. https://doi.org/10.2307/201996
Hout, M., & Fischer, C. S. (2002). Why More Americans Have No Religious Preference: Politics and Generations. American Sociological Review, 67(2), 165–190. https://doi.org/10.2307/3088891
Jenkins, J. R. (2020). Is Religiosity a Black Thing?: Reading the Black None in Octavia E. Butler’s “The Book of Martha.” Pacific Coast Philology, 55(1), 5–22. https://doi.org/10.5325/pacicoasphil.55.1.0005
Jung, J. H. (2015). Sense of Divine Involvement and Sense of Meaning in Life: Religious Tradition as a Contingency. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 54(1), 119–133. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24644249
Kalmoe, N. P. (2020). Uses and Abuses of Ideology in Political Psychology. Political Psychology, 41(4), 771–793. http://www.jstor.org/stable/45295275
Lim, C., MacGregor, C. A., & Putnam, R. D. (2010). Secular and Liminal: Discovering Heterogeneity Among Religious Nones. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 49(4), 596–618. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40959050
Lim, C. (2015). Religion and Subjective Well-Being Across Religious Traditions: Evidence from 1.3 Million Americans. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 54(4), 684–701. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26651391
Miller, C. (2016). “Spiritual But Not Religious”: Rethinking the Legal Definition of Religion. Virginia Law Review, 102(3), 833–894. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43923324
Olson, P. J., & Beckworth, D. (2011). Religious Change and Stability: Seasonality in Church Attendance from the 1940s to the 2000s. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 50(2), 388–396. http://www.jstor.org/stable/41307082
Packard, J., & Ferguson, T. W. (2019). Being Done: Why People Leave the Church, But Not Their Faith. Sociological Perspectives, 62(4), 499–517. https://www.jstor.org/stable/26746198
Salinas, A. (2010). Political Philosophy in Borges: Fallibility, Liberal Anarchism, and Civic Ethics. The Review of Politics, 72(2), 299–324. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20780307
Schnell, T., & Keenan, W. J. F. (2011). Meaning-Making in an Atheist World. Archiv Für Religionspsychologie / Archive for the Psychology of Religion, 33(1), 55–78. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23918907
Sepulvado, B., Hachen, D., Penta, M., & Lizardo, O. (2015). Social Affiliation from Religious Disaffiliation: Evidence of Selective Mixing Among Youth with No Religious Preference During the Transition to College. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 54(4), 833–841. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26651399
Sheils, Dean. (1980). The Great Ancestors Are Watching A Cross-Cultural Study of Superior Ancestral Religion. Sociological Analysis, 41(3), 247–257. https://doi.org/10.2307/3710401
Strhan, A., & Shillitoe, R. (2019). The Stickiness of Non-Religion? Intergenerational Transmission and the Formation of Non-Religious Identities in Childhood. Sociology, 53(6), 1094–1110. https://www.jstor.org/stable/26972328
Tamney, J. B., Powell, S., & Johnson, S. (1989). Innovation Theory and Religious Nones. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 28(2), 216–229. https://doi.org/10.2307/1387060
Thiessen, J., & Wilkins-Laflamme, S. (2017). Becoming a Religious None: Irreligious Socialization and Disaffiliation. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 56(1), 64–82. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26651857
Vernon, G. M. (1968). The Religious “Nones”: A Neglected Category. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 7(2), 219–229. https://doi.org/10.2307/1384629
Wilkins-Laflamme, S. (2016). Secularization and the Wider Gap in Values and Personal Religiosity Between the Religious and Nonreligious. Journal for the Scientific Study of Religion, 55(4), 717–736. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26651610
Zwingmann, C., & Gottschling, S. (2015). Religiosity, Spirituality, and God Concepts: Interreligious and Interdenominational Comparisons Within a German Sample. Archiv Für Religionspsychologie / Archive for the Psychology of Religion, 37(1), 98–116. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43973388
Neville Buch
Historian,
President, Sea of Faith in Australia Inc. (SoFiA)
Professional Historians Australia (Queensland)
Australian and New Zealand History of Education Society (ANZHES)
Convenor, Sociology of Education Thematic Group, The Australian Sociological Association (TASA).
President, Southern Brisbane Suburban Forum (SBSF).
Director, Brisbane Southside History Network (BSHN).
MPHA (Qld), Ph.D. (History) UQ., Grad. Dip. Arts (Philosophy) Melb., Grad. Dip. (Education) UQ.
by Neville Buch | Feb 16, 2022 | Article, Blog, Concepts in Educationalist Thought Series
“Many educators and administrators feel that university public service programming will assume an even larger role in the university community due to declining enrollment and public demands for relevance.” Robert Sellers. Methodology for Evaluating University Public Service Outreach to State and Local Government, in State & Local Government Review, May 1979, Vol. 11, No. 2 (May, 1979), pp. 64-69 (http://www.jstor.org/stable/4354649).
So was said in 1979. Community education is a public service, substantially. However, the article of the past is very revealing in how we have not progressed in community education as a public service. “For example, said Robert Sellers, “it might be established that a public service unit with less than two full-time professionals would rank below standard for that characteristic.”
A global conversation needs to open up on the community education, and include the many visions of community education, and which would embrace differences.
More than that the practice in the new community education model(s) need to become formative. My thinking here is informed by the knowledge of how the histories have shaped community education. There are several examples I can give, but here is one.
In the early 20th century community education, across Commonwealth countries, was substantive in the form of Technical Colleges, Schools of Art, Mechanic Institutes, royal societies, and ideological associations – Freethinkers, Rationalists, and Church lecture series. By the mid-century that momentum is eroded, and community education is largely reduced to technical arts at the tech colleges. In Australia there was never a history of the American state community colleges, and the liberal arts colleges which emerged in the mid-West. The early 21st century ‘global’ has changed the dynamics with the emergence of online educative communities. However, it struggles in the 1990s-created neo-liberal economy and institutional constant habits, where the talk is generally innovation but without structural change. An example of innovation with structural change is the University of Melbourne’s Melbourne Model (2005-2015).
Where we need to look to examine the challenges, is in the relationship between the universities and community education. The informal history of community education goes back a long way – catechisms, political meetings in the public square, Sunday schools, and so forth. To different measures, these gatherings were popular movements. The universities ebbed and flowed through these popular movements, and the academy was both influenced popular movements and was influenced by such movements. In the 20th century the universities took a larger leadership role in community education. This was particularly seen in the organisation of the Workers Educational Association. However, the momentum withered in the last quarter of the century. This coincided with the development of university’s correspondence courses, with community members obtaining degrees through programs in mail packages, radio, and television. This process was replaced, in this century, by the online collaborative university educational programs, such as Open University. In this case the degrees are badged as generic across the university partners. Where does that leave community education?
In a neo-liberal economy, it means that many community members are still left out of the university’s ‘open’ offerings. That means that many communities members look to community education as a free hobby, a plaything with no educative concern. In such an environment, lifelong learning is significantly diminished.
That is the current challenge for community educators and facilitators, as well as for corporate owners of the platforms that operated to run community education programs.
SOURCES
Articles
Barcan, Alan. Whatever Happened to Adult Education? AQ – Australian Quarterly, vol. 79, no. 2, 2007, pp. 29–36,40.
Binnion, Denis. One Hundred Years of the WEA. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 53, no. 3, 2013, pp. 478–481.
Binnion, Denis. What’s New in Course Programming? a Brief Analysis of WEA Course Programs 1917/ 1976. Australian Journal of Adult and Community Education, vol. 37, no. 1, 1997, pp. 27–32.
Belzil, C., & Leonardi, M. Risk Aversion and Schooling Decisions. Annals of Economics and Statistics, (111/112), 2013, 35-70. doi:10.2307/23646326
Brown, P. The Globalisation of Positional Competition? Sociology, 34(4), 2000, 633–653. http://www.jstor.org/stable/42856224
Buch, Neville. The Changing Definition of Peace, Part 1: The Status Quo of Thinking in Queensland during the Armistice. Queensland History Journal, Royal Historical Society Queensland. Volume 24, No. 1, May 2019.
Buch, Neville. The Changing Definition of Peace, Part 2: The Shifting of Thinking in Queensland during the Armistice. Queensland History Journal, Royal Historical Society Queensland. Volume 24, No. 1, May 2019.
Buch, Neville. Economic Rationalism and University Course Pricing 1989-2020, for Australian Policy and History, published online, August 3, 2020
Neville Buch. Finding Peace from the Culture-History War: A Historiographical Message for the Times. Academia Letters, Article No. 1916., 2021, https://doi.org/10.20935/AL1916.
Buch, Neville. Review Essay of Rocha, Christina, Mark Hutchinson and Kathleen Openshaw (eds.), Australian Pentecostal and Charismatic Movements, Brill Publications, 2020, p. 304, ISBN 9789004425781, Journal for the Academic Study of Religion, pending 2022
Chattopadhyay, S. The Market in Higher Education: Concern for Equity and Quality. Economic and Political Weekly,44(29), 2009, 53-61. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/40279288
Darian‐Smith, Kate. Up the country: Histories and communities, Australian Historical Studies, 33:118, 2002, 90-99, DOI: 10.1080/10314610208596182
Duncan, W. G. K. “Agenda for a National Association: Blast from the Past. [Reprinted from the Australian Journal of Adult Education, V.1, July 1961]. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 40, no. 3, 2000, 198–207.
Friesen, G., & Taksa, L. Workers’ Education in Australia and Canada: A Comparative Approach to Labour’s Cultural History. Labour History, (71), 1996, 170-197. doi:10.2307/27516453
Gary-Bobo, R., & Trannoy, A. Efficient Tuition Fees and Examinations. Journal of the European Economic Association, 6(6), 2008, 1211-1243. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/40282703
Greenwood, Gordon. The present state of history teaching and research in Australian universities: An estimate, Historical Studies: Australia and New Zealand, 6:23, 1953, 324-338, DOI: 10.1080/10314615408595002
Gwenda Tavan. ‘Good neighbours’: Community organisations, migrant assimilation and Australian society and culture, 1950–1961, Australian Historical Studies, 27:109, 1997, 77-89, DOI: 10.1080/10314619708596044
Holford, John. The Misuses of Sustainability: Adult Education, Citizenship and the Dead Hand of Neoliberalism. International Review of Education, vol. 62, no. 5, 2016, pp. 541–561.
Jamal, T., Taillon, J., & Dredge, D. Sustainable tourism pedagogy and academic-community collaboration: A progressive service-learning approach. Tourism and Hospitality Research, 11(2), 2011, 133–147. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23745474
Jones, Adrian. Teaching History at University through Communities of Inquiry, Australian Historical Studies, 42:2, 2011, 168-193, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2010.531747
Khodyakov, D., Stockdale, S., Jones, A., Mango, J., Jones, F., & Lizaola, E. On Measuring Community Participation in Research. Health Education & Behavior, 40(3), 2013, 346–354. http://www.jstor.org/stable/45088088
Lack, John. Residence, workplace, community: Local history in metropolitan Melbourne, Historical Studies, 19:74, 1980, 16-40, DOI: 10.1080/10314618008595622
Lawton, Colin R. Early Memories of the Australian Association of Adult Education: Blast from the Past. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 40, no. 3, 2000, pp. 196–197.
Lecompte, M. D. Collisions of culture: Academic culture in the neoliberal university. Learning and Teaching: The International Journal of Higher Education in the Social Sciences, 7(1), 2014, 57–78. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24717955
Marginson, Simon. Competition in Higher Education in the Post-Hilmer Era. The Australian Quarterly, 68(4), 1996, 22-35. doi:10.2307/20634749
Marginson, Simon. Imagining Ivy: Pitfalls in the Privatization of Higher Education in Australia. Comparative Education Review,41(4), 1997, 460-480. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/1189004
Martin Crotty & Erik Eklund. History as Service Teaching Possibilities and Pitfalls, History Australia, 3:2, 47, 2006, 1-47.10, DOI: 10.2104/ha060047
Martin Crotty & Paul Sendziuk. The Numbers Game: History Staffing in Australian and New Zealand Universities, Australian Historical Studies, 50:3, 2019, 354-377, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2019.1601750
Matthews, J. Education for Femininity: Domestic Arts Education in South Australia. Labour History, (45), 1983, 30-53. doi:10.2307/27508604
Meyer, H. Universal, Entrepreneurial, and Soulless? The New University as a Contested Institution. Comparative Education Review, 46(3), 2002, 339-347. doi:10.1086/341161
Milana, Marcella, et al. The Role of Adult Education and Learning Policy in Fostering Societal Sustainability. International Review of Education, vol. 62, no. 5, 2016, pp. 523–540.
Morris, Roger K. The WEA in Sydney, 1913 – 2013: Achievements; Controversies; and an Inherent Difficulty. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 53, no. 3, 2013, pp. 487–498.
Muste, C. P. Reframing Polarization: Social Groups and “Culture Wars.” PS: Political Science and Politics, 47(2), 2014, 432–442. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43284567
Newton, Michael. A Century of Learning: WEA Sydney 1913-2013. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 53, no. 3, 2013, pp. 482–486.
Perry, B. Universities and Cities: Governance, Institutions and Mediation. Built Environment (1978-), 37(3), 2011, 244–259. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23290044
Reid, A. Exploring values in sustainable development. Teaching Geography, 21(4), 1996, 168-171. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/23754452
Ryan, M. Productions of space: Civic participation of young people at university. British Educational Research Journal,37(6), 2011,1015-1031. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/23077021
Rothschild, M., & White, L. The Analytics of the Pricing of Higher Education and Other Services in Which the Customers Are Inputs. Journal of Political Economy, 103(3), 1995, 573-586. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/2138699
Ryan, Y. Higher Education as a Business: Lessons From The Corporate World. Minerva, 39(1), 2001, 115-135. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/41821179
Singh, P., & Doherty, C. Global Cultural Flows and Pedagogic Dilemmas: Teaching in the Global University Contact Zone. TESOL Quarterly, 38(1), 2004, 9–42. https://doi.org/10.2307/3588257
Shipp, George, and Newman, Mike. An Open Letter: Mike Newman’s Defining the Enemy and Liberal Adult Education. [and Response to An Open Letter. Collection of Two Articles]. Australian Journal of Adult and Community Education, vol. 37, no. 1, 1997, pp. 57–62.
Stone, D. Private challenges to public goods: Transformations in Australian higher education. The Australian Quarterly, 60(1), 1988, 40-62. Retrieved April 29, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/41317987
Sutherland, Heather. The Problematic Authority of (World) History. Journal of World History 18, no. 4, 2007, 491–522. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20079450.
Sutton, W., & Kolaja, J. Elements of Community Action. Social Forces, 38(4), 1960, 325-331. doi:10.2307/2573042
Thomas, Amy, Hannah Forsyth & Andrew G. Bonnell. ‘The dice are loaded’: history, solidarity and precarity in Australian universities, History Australia, 17:1, 21-39, 2020, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2020.1717350
Tosh, J. Public History, Civic Engagement and the Historical Profession in Britain. History, 99, 2 (335), 2014, 191–212. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24429936
Vick, Malcolm. Community, state and the provision of schools in mid‐nineteenth century South Australia, Australian Historical Studies, 25:98, 1992, 53-71, DOI: 10.1080/10314619208595893
Wade, Stephen. The Glory Of Education’: One Hundred Years Of The Workers’ Educational Association. Contemporary Review, vol. 283, no. 1654, 2003, pp. 285–288.
BOOK CHAPTERS
Buch, Neville (2021). The Intellectual Ethos of Charles Strong in Queensland 1855-1917, in Marion Maddox, Charles Strong’s Australian Church: Christian Social Activism, 1885–1917, University of Melbourne Press.
Edmonds, P. (2015). Whither the universities. In Tilting at Windmills: The literary magazine in Australia, 1968-2012 (pp. 153-154). South Australia: University of Adelaide Press. Retrieved May 1, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.20851/j.ctt1sq5wf6.15
Mckillop. A.B. ((1994) Character and Conduct (pp. 83-100) in Mckillop, A., Matters of Mind: The University in Ontario, 1791-1951. Toronto; Buffalo; London: University of Toronto Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.3138/j.ctvcj2q67
BOOKS
Buch Neville (2014). Celebrating 40 Years. St Thomas More College, God’s Servant First (1974-2014). St Thomas More College. (pp. 123).
Buch Neville (2015). No Regrets in the Evening of Life: The History of Junction Park State School (1888-2013). Boolarong Press. (pp. 459).
Buch Neville (2016). A Quest for a Fair Go: A History of the KSC in Queensland (with Beryl Roberts). Stafford, Qld. The Knights of the Southern Cross (Qld). (pp. 281)
Denniss, Richard (2021) Econobabble: How to decode political spin and economic nonsense, Black Inc.
Emison, Mary (2013). Degrees for a New Generation: Marking the Melbourne Model, University of Melbourne Press
Francis X. Hartigan (edited, 1989). History and Humanities: Essays in Honour of Wilbur S. Shepperson, University of Nevada Press
Grawe, Nathan D. (2021). The Agile College: How Institutions Successfully Navigate Demographic Changes, John Hopkins University Press .
Habermas, Jürgen (1992) Communication and the Evolution of Society, Polity Press
Hai, A.A., et al (edited, 2020) Reimagining Teaching in Early 20th Century, Springer
Hayot, Eric (2021). Humanist Reason: A History, An Argument, A Plan, Columbia University Press
Kupfer, Antonia (2012). Globalisation, higher education, the labour market and inequality. Routledge, London
Lawrence, Jon (2019). Me, me, me? : the search for community in post-war England, Oxford University Press, Oxford, England
Macintye, Stuart (2006). How Organisations Connect: Investing in Communication, Melbourne University Press
Macintye,Stuart (2010). The Poor Relations: A History of Social Sciences in Australia, Melbourne University Press
Macintye, Stuart (2016). Life After Dawkins: The University of Melbourne in the Unified National System of Higher Education, Melbourne University Press
Mandler, Peter (2020). The Crisis of the Meritocracy: Britain’s Transition to Mass Education since the Second World War, Oxford University Press
Marginson, Simon (2016). Higher Education and the Common Good. Melbourne University Publishing
Marginson, Simon (1993). Education and Public Policy in Australia. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge [England] ; Melbourne
Marginson, Simon (1997). Markets in Education. Allen & Unwin, St. Leonards, N.S.W
Marginson, Simon. (2016). The Dream Is Over: The Crisis of Clark Kerr’s California Idea of Higher Education. Oakland, California: University of California Press.
Newton, Michael, et al (1997). In Touch with a New World: Celebrating Adult Learning at WEA Sydney, State Library of NSW, Mitchell Library.
Reitter, Paul and Chad Wellmon (2021). Permanent Crisis: The Humanities in a Disenchanted Age, The University of Chicago Press
Roberts, Jon H. and James Turner (2000). The Sacred and the Secular University, with an Introduction by John F. Wilson. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN: 0-6910-1556-2
Sandel, Michael (2020). The Tyranny of Merit: What’s Become of the Common Good? Penguin Random House
Teese, Richard (2000). Academic Success and Social Power: Examinations and Inequality, Melbourne University Press
Willetts, David (2017). A University Education, Oxford University Press
William Clark (2006). Academic Charisma and the Origins of the Research University, University of Chicago Press
University Campus Education Knowledge School Concept
Image: Photo 75687496 / Community Education © Rawpixelimages | Dreamstime.com
by Neville Buch | May 20, 2024 | American-Australian Relational History, Concepts in Educationalist Thought Series, Important Public Statement, The Importance Of History In Our Own Lives?
Dear Friends, and I thank Graham Perrett’s office for its recent kind support, and several friends who made sure I have not gone under,
So,
I said it back in March with the emerging American sources on the ground, so
why does the Queensland powers-that-be give me the silent treatment when
I am on the top of the intellectual “game” in this state? Is it the corruption in the thinking?????????????
For intelligence, see the reference of Henry Reining (1959). Your (I am talking to the uncompassionate and unkind) thinking is so out-of-date, spiralling around in ignorance. See how old some of the references are.
Centrism (now called neopopulism)
REFERENCES (TOP SELECTION — WRITERS WHO ARE BETTER THAN THE Stupid (made stupid in arrogance) “SMARTS”)
David Leonhardt (2024). A New Centrism Is Rising in Washington, The New York Times, May 19, 2024.
Neville Buch (2024). The American-Australian Center-Centre, Dr Neville Buch ABN: 86703686642, March 29, 2024.
******
Anderson, T. J. (1965). Pressure Groups and Intergovernmental Relations. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 359, 116–126. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1035114
Arrington, T. S. (1975). Some Effects of Political Experience on Issue Consciousness and Issue Partisanship among Tuscon Party Activists. American Journal of Political Science, 19(4), 695–702. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110722
Barnes, S. H., & Pierce, R. (1971). Public Opinion and Political Preferences in France and Italy. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(4), 643–660. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110046
Bell, R. (1969). The Determinants of Psychological Involvement in Politics: A Causal Analysis. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 13(2), 237–253. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110176
Bone, H. A. (1958). Political Parties and Pressure Group Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 319, 73–83. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1032438
Buchanan, W. (1965). Politics and Federalism: Party or Anti-Party? The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 359, 107–115. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1035113
Buchanan, W. (1962). Federal Aid to Education on the Conservative-Liberal Scale. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 344, 55–64. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033075
Buck, J. V. (1972). Presidential Coattails and Congressional Loyalty. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(3), 460–472. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110093
Charlesworth, J. C. (1967). National Character in the Perspective of Political Science. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 370, 23–29. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1038047
Clausen, A. R. (1972). State Party Influence on Congressional Policy Decision. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(1), 77–101. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110411
Cornwell, E. E. (1964). Bosses, Machines, and Ethnic Groups. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 27–39. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036061
Daalder, H., & Irwin, G. A. (1974). Interests and Institutions in the Netherlands: An Assessment by the People and by Parliament. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 413, 58–71. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1040567
Dobson, D., & Meeter, D. A. (1974). Alternative Markov Models for Describing Change in Party Identification. American Journal of Political Science, 18(3), 487–500. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110627
Ebersole, L. (1960). Religion and Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 332, 101–111. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033792
Grant, L. V. (1973). Specialization as a Strategy in Legislative Decision-Making. American Journal of Political Science, 17(1), 123–147. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110477
Ginsberg, B. (1972). Critical Elections and the Substance of Party Conflict: 1844-1968. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(4), 603–625. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110379
Greenstein, F. I. (1964). The Changing Pattern of Urban Party Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 1–13. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036059
Gump, W. R. (1971). The Functions of Patronage in American Party Politics: An Empirical Reappraisal. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(1), 87–107. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110251
Jackson, J. E. (1975). Issues, Party Choices, and Presidential Votes. American Journal of Political Science, 19(2), 161–185. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110431
Jones, C. O. (1974). Between Party Battalions and Committee Suzerainty. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 411, 158–168. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1041009
Hinckley, B. (1972). Coalitions in Congress: Size and Ideological Distance. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(2), 197–207. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110055
Hinderaker, I. (1966). Political Party Officials: Responsiveness to the Public. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 363, 28–35. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036465
Kammerer, G. M., & DeGrove, J. M. (1964). Urban Leadership during Change. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 95–106. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036067
Koeppen, S. R. (1969). The Republican Radical Right. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 382, 73–82. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1037116
Kornberg, A., Smith, J., Clarke, M.-J., & Clarke, H. D. (1973). Participation in Local Party Organizations in the United States and Canada. American Journal of Political Science, 17(1), 23–47. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110473
Knoke, D. (1974). Religion, Stratification and Politics: American in the 1960s. American Journal of Political Science, 18(2), 331–345. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110705
Lenhart, R. F., & Schriftgiesser, K. (1958). Management in Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 319, 32–40. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1032434
Lowenthal, R. (1963). Factors of Unity and Factors of Conflict. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 349, 106–116. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1035701
Ordeshook, P. C. (1970). Extensions to a Model of the Electoral Process and Implications for the Theory of Responsible Parties. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 14(1), 43–70. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110392
Orlans, H. (1971). The Political Uses of Social Research. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 394, 28–35. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1039287
Pempel, T. J. (1974). The Bureaucratization of Policymaking in Postwar Japan. American Journal of Political Science, 18(4), 647–664. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110551
Pierce, J. C. (1970). Party Identification and the Changing Role of Ideology in American Politics. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 14(1), 25–42. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110391
Pomper, G. (1967). “If Elected, I Promise”: American Party Platforms. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 11(3), 318–352. https://doi.org/10.2307/2108616
Przeworski, A., & Sprague, J. (1971). Concepts in Search of Explicit Formulation: A Study in Measurement. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(2), 183–218. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110270
Riedel, J. A. (1964). Boss and Faction. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 14–26. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036060
Reining, H. (1959). The Government Contract as an Administrative Device. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 323, 68–79. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033527
Shannon, J. B. (1962). Conservatism. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 344, 13–24. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033071
Silvert, K. H. (1965). Parties and the Masses. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 358, 101–108. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036360
Stillman, E. O. (1958). The Beginning of the “Thaw,” 1953-1955. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 317, 12–21. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1031073
Weeks, K. M. (1970). Members of Parliament and the New Zealand Ombudsman System. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 14(4), 673–686. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110359
Wellhofer, E. S. (1974). Political Parties as “Communities of Fate”: Tests with Argentine Party Elites. American Journal of Political Science, 18(2), 347–363. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110706
Wellhofer, E. S., & Hennessey, T. M. (1974). Political Party Development: Institutionalization, Leadership Recruitment, and Behavior. American Journal of Political Science, 18(1), 135–165. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110658
Wilcox, W. (1965). Politicians, Bureaucrats, and Development in India. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 358, 114–122. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036362
Featured Image: American-Australian-Intellectual-Cultural-Relations.png