History and Practice of Community Education. CET No. 1.

History and Practice of Community Education. CET No. 1.

“Many educators and administrators feel that university public service programming will assume an even larger role in the university community due to declining enrollment and public demands for relevance.” Robert Sellers. Methodology for Evaluating University Public Service Outreach to State and Local Government, in State & Local Government Review, May 1979, Vol. 11, No. 2 (May, 1979), pp. 64-69 (http://www.jstor.org/stable/4354649).

 

So was said in 1979. Community education is a public service, substantially.  However, the article of the past is very revealing in how we have not progressed in community education as a public service. “For example, said Robert Sellers, “it might be established that a public service unit with less than two full-time professionals would rank below standard for that characteristic.”

 

A global conversation needs to open up on the community education, and include the many visions of community education, and which would embrace differences.

 

More than that the practice in the new community education model(s) need to become formative. My thinking here is informed by the knowledge of how the histories have shaped community education. There are several examples I can give, but here is one.

 

In the early 20th century community education, across Commonwealth countries, was substantive in the form of Technical Colleges, Schools of Art, Mechanic Institutes, royal societies, and ideological associations – Freethinkers, Rationalists, and Church lecture series. By the mid-century that momentum is eroded, and community education is largely reduced to technical arts at the tech colleges. In Australia there was never a history of the American state community colleges, and the liberal arts colleges which emerged in the mid-West. The early 21st century ‘global’ has changed the dynamics with the emergence of online educative communities. However, it struggles in the 1990s-created neo-liberal economy and institutional constant habits, where the talk is generally innovation but without structural change. An example of innovation with structural change is the University of Melbourne’s Melbourne Model (2005-2015).

 

Where we need to look to examine the challenges, is in the relationship between the universities and community education. The informal history of community education goes back a long way – catechisms, political meetings in the public square, Sunday schools, and so forth. To different measures, these gatherings were popular movements. The universities ebbed and flowed through these popular movements, and the academy was both influenced popular movements and was influenced by such movements. In the 20th century the universities took a larger leadership role in community education. This was particularly seen in the organisation of the Workers Educational Association. However, the momentum withered in the last quarter of the century. This coincided with the development of university’s correspondence courses, with community members obtaining degrees through programs in mail packages, radio, and television. This process was replaced, in this century, by the online collaborative university educational programs, such as Open University. In this case the degrees are badged as generic across the university partners. Where does that leave community education?

 

In a neo-liberal economy, it means that many community members are still left out of the university’s ‘open’ offerings. That means that many communities members look to community education as a free hobby, a plaything with no educative concern. In such an environment, lifelong learning is significantly diminished.

 

That is the current challenge for community educators and facilitators, as well as for corporate owners of the platforms that operated to run community education programs.

 

SOURCES

Articles

Barcan, Alan. Whatever Happened to Adult Education? AQ – Australian Quarterly, vol. 79, no. 2, 2007, pp. 29–36,40.

Binnion, Denis. One Hundred Years of the WEA. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 53, no. 3, 2013, pp. 478–481.

Binnion, Denis. What’s New in Course Programming? a Brief Analysis of WEA Course Programs 1917/ 1976. Australian Journal of Adult and Community Education, vol. 37, no. 1, 1997, pp. 27–32.

Belzil, C., & Leonardi, M. Risk Aversion and Schooling Decisions. Annals of Economics and Statistics, (111/112), 2013, 35-70. doi:10.2307/23646326

Brown, P. The Globalisation of Positional Competition? Sociology, 34(4), 2000, 633–653. http://www.jstor.org/stable/42856224

Buch, Neville. The Changing Definition of Peace, Part 1: The Status Quo of Thinking in Queensland during the Armistice. Queensland History Journal, Royal Historical Society Queensland. Volume 24, No. 1, May 2019.

Buch, Neville. The Changing Definition of Peace, Part 2: The Shifting of Thinking in Queensland during the Armistice. Queensland History Journal, Royal Historical Society Queensland. Volume 24, No. 1, May 2019.

Buch, Neville. Economic Rationalism and University Course Pricing 1989-2020, for Australian Policy and History, published online, August 3, 2020

Neville Buch.  Finding Peace from the Culture-History War: A Historiographical Message for the Times. Academia Letters, Article No. 1916., 2021, https://doi.org/10.20935/AL1916.

Buch, Neville. Review Essay of Rocha, Christina, Mark Hutchinson and Kathleen Openshaw (eds.), Australian Pentecostal and Charismatic Movements, Brill Publications, 2020, p. 304, ISBN 9789004425781, Journal for the Academic Study of Religion, pending 2022

Chattopadhyay, S. The Market in Higher Education: Concern for Equity and Quality. Economic and Political Weekly,44(29), 2009, 53-61. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/40279288

Darian‐Smith, Kate. Up the country: Histories and communities, Australian Historical Studies, 33:118, 2002, 90-99, DOI: 10.1080/10314610208596182

Duncan, W. G. K. “Agenda for a National Association: Blast from the Past. [Reprinted from the Australian Journal of Adult Education, V.1, July 1961]. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 40, no. 3, 2000, 198–207.

Friesen, G., & Taksa, L. Workers’ Education in Australia and Canada: A Comparative Approach to Labour’s Cultural History. Labour History, (71), 1996, 170-197. doi:10.2307/27516453

Gary-Bobo, R., & Trannoy, A. Efficient Tuition Fees and Examinations. Journal of the European Economic Association, 6(6), 2008, 1211-1243. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/40282703

Greenwood, Gordon. The present state of history teaching and research in Australian universities: An estimate, Historical Studies: Australia and New Zealand, 6:23, 1953, 324-338, DOI: 10.1080/10314615408595002

Gwenda Tavan. ‘Good neighbours’: Community organisations, migrant assimilation and Australian society and culture, 1950–1961, Australian Historical Studies, 27:109, 1997, 77-89, DOI: 10.1080/10314619708596044

Holford, John. The Misuses of Sustainability: Adult Education, Citizenship and the Dead Hand of Neoliberalism. International Review of Education, vol. 62, no. 5, 2016, pp. 541–561.

Jamal, T., Taillon, J., & Dredge, D. Sustainable tourism pedagogy and academic-community collaboration: A progressive service-learning approach. Tourism and Hospitality Research, 11(2), 2011, 133–147. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23745474

Jones, Adrian. Teaching History at University through Communities of Inquiry, Australian Historical Studies, 42:2, 2011, 168-193, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2010.531747

Khodyakov, D., Stockdale, S., Jones, A., Mango, J., Jones, F., & Lizaola, E. On Measuring Community Participation in Research. Health Education & Behavior, 40(3), 2013, 346–354. http://www.jstor.org/stable/45088088

Lack, John. Residence, workplace, community: Local history in metropolitan Melbourne, Historical Studies, 19:74, 1980, 16-40, DOI: 10.1080/10314618008595622

Lawton, Colin R. Early Memories of the Australian Association of Adult Education: Blast from the Past.  Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 40, no. 3, 2000, pp. 196–197.

Lecompte, M. D. Collisions of culture: Academic culture in the neoliberal university. Learning and Teaching: The International Journal of Higher Education in the Social Sciences, 7(1), 2014, 57–78. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24717955

Marginson, Simon. Competition in Higher Education in the Post-Hilmer Era. The Australian Quarterly, 68(4), 1996, 22-35. doi:10.2307/20634749

Marginson, Simon. Imagining Ivy: Pitfalls in the Privatization of Higher Education in Australia. Comparative Education Review,41(4), 1997, 460-480. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/1189004

Martin Crotty & Erik Eklund. History as Service Teaching Possibilities and Pitfalls, History Australia, 3:2, 47, 2006, 1-47.10, DOI: 10.2104/ha060047

Martin Crotty & Paul Sendziuk. The Numbers Game: History Staffing in Australian and New Zealand Universities, Australian Historical Studies, 50:3, 2019, 354-377, DOI: 10.1080/1031461X.2019.1601750

Matthews, J. Education for Femininity: Domestic Arts Education in South Australia. Labour History, (45), 1983, 30-53. doi:10.2307/27508604

Meyer, H. Universal, Entrepreneurial, and Soulless? The New University as a Contested Institution. Comparative Education Review, 46(3), 2002, 339-347. doi:10.1086/341161

Milana, Marcella, et al. The Role of Adult Education and Learning Policy in Fostering Societal Sustainability. International Review of Education, vol. 62, no. 5, 2016, pp. 523–540.

Morris, Roger K. The WEA in Sydney, 1913 – 2013: Achievements; Controversies; and an Inherent Difficulty. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 53, no. 3, 2013, pp. 487–498.

Muste, C. P. Reframing Polarization: Social Groups and “Culture Wars.” PS: Political Science and Politics, 47(2), 2014, 432–442. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43284567

Newton, Michael. A Century of Learning: WEA Sydney 1913-2013. Australian Journal of Adult Learning, vol. 53, no. 3, 2013, pp. 482–486.

Perry, B. Universities and Cities: Governance, Institutions and Mediation. Built Environment (1978-), 37(3), 2011, 244–259. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23290044

Reid, A. Exploring values in sustainable development. Teaching Geography, 21(4), 1996, 168-171. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/23754452

Ryan, M. Productions of space: Civic participation of young people at university. British Educational Research Journal,37(6), 2011,1015-1031. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/23077021

Rothschild, M., & White, L. The Analytics of the Pricing of Higher Education and Other Services in Which the Customers Are Inputs. Journal of Political Economy, 103(3), 1995, 573-586. Retrieved June 22, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/2138699

Ryan, Y. Higher Education as a Business: Lessons From The Corporate World. Minerva, 39(1), 2001, 115-135. Retrieved April 28, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/41821179

Singh, P., & Doherty, C. Global Cultural Flows and Pedagogic Dilemmas: Teaching in the Global University Contact Zone. TESOL Quarterly, 38(1), 2004, 9–42. https://doi.org/10.2307/3588257

Shipp, George, and Newman, Mike. An Open Letter: Mike Newman’s Defining the Enemy and Liberal Adult Education. [and Response to An Open Letter. Collection of Two Articles]. Australian Journal of Adult and Community Education, vol. 37, no. 1, 1997, pp. 57–62.

Stone, D. Private challenges to public goods: Transformations in Australian higher education. The Australian Quarterly, 60(1), 1988, 40-62. Retrieved April 29, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/41317987

Sutherland, Heather. The Problematic Authority of (World) History. Journal of World History 18, no. 4, 2007, 491–522. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20079450.

Sutton, W., & Kolaja, J. Elements of Community Action. Social Forces, 38(4), 1960, 325-331. doi:10.2307/2573042

Thomas, Amy, Hannah Forsyth & Andrew G. Bonnell. ‘The dice are loaded’: history, solidarity and precarity in Australian universities, History Australia, 17:1, 21-39, 2020, DOI: 10.1080/14490854.2020.1717350

Tosh, J. Public History, Civic Engagement and the Historical Profession in Britain. History, 99, 2 (335), 2014, 191–212. http://www.jstor.org/stable/24429936

Vick, Malcolm. Community, state and the provision of schools in mid‐nineteenth century South Australia, Australian Historical Studies, 25:98, 1992, 53-71, DOI: 10.1080/10314619208595893

Wade, Stephen. The Glory Of Education’: One Hundred Years Of The Workers’ Educational Association. Contemporary Review, vol. 283, no. 1654, 2003, pp. 285–288.

 

BOOK CHAPTERS

Buch, Neville (2021). The Intellectual Ethos of Charles Strong in Queensland 1855-1917, in Marion Maddox, Charles Strong’s Australian Church: Christian Social Activism, 1885–1917, University of Melbourne Press.

Edmonds, P. (2015). Whither the universities. In Tilting at Windmills: The literary magazine in Australia, 1968-2012 (pp. 153-154). South Australia: University of Adelaide Press. Retrieved May 1, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.20851/j.ctt1sq5wf6.15

Mckillop. A.B. ((1994) Character and Conduct (pp. 83-100) in Mckillop, A., Matters of Mind: The University in Ontario, 1791-1951. Toronto; Buffalo; London: University of Toronto Press. Retrieved May 8, 2020, from www.jstor.org/stable/10.3138/j.ctvcj2q67

 

BOOKS

Buch Neville (2014). Celebrating 40 Years.  St Thomas More College, God’s Servant First (1974-2014). St Thomas More College. (pp. 123).

Buch Neville (2015). No Regrets in the Evening of Life: The History of Junction Park State School (1888-2013). Boolarong Press. (pp. 459).

Buch Neville (2016). A Quest for a Fair Go: A History of the KSC in Queensland (with Beryl Roberts). Stafford, Qld. The Knights of the Southern Cross (Qld). (pp. 281)

Denniss, Richard (2021) Econobabble: How to decode political spin and economic nonsense, Black Inc.

Emison, Mary (2013). Degrees for a New Generation: Marking the Melbourne Model, University of Melbourne Press

Francis X. Hartigan (edited, 1989). History and Humanities: Essays in Honour of Wilbur S. Shepperson, University of Nevada Press

Grawe, Nathan D. (2021). The Agile College: How Institutions Successfully Navigate Demographic Changes, John Hopkins University Press .

Habermas, JĂŒrgen (1992) Communication and the Evolution of Society, Polity Press

Hai, A.A., et al (edited, 2020) Reimagining Teaching in Early 20th Century, Springer

Hayot, Eric (2021). Humanist Reason: A History, An Argument, A Plan, Columbia University Press

Kupfer, Antonia (2012). Globalisation, higher education, the labour market and inequality. Routledge, London

Lawrence, Jon (2019). Me, me, me? : the search for community in post-war England, Oxford University Press, Oxford, England

Macintye, Stuart (2006). How Organisations Connect: Investing in Communication, Melbourne University Press

Macintye,Stuart (2010). The Poor Relations: A History of Social Sciences in Australia, Melbourne University Press

Macintye, Stuart (2016). Life After Dawkins: The University of Melbourne in the Unified National System of Higher Education, Melbourne University Press

Mandler, Peter (2020). The Crisis of the Meritocracy: Britain’s Transition to Mass Education since the Second World War, Oxford University Press

Marginson, Simon  (2016). Higher Education and the Common Good. Melbourne University Publishing

Marginson, Simon (1993). Education and Public Policy in Australia. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge [England] ; Melbourne

Marginson, Simon (1997). Markets in Education. Allen & Unwin, St. Leonards, N.S.W

Marginson, Simon. (2016). The Dream Is Over: The Crisis of Clark Kerr’s California Idea of Higher Education. Oakland, California: University of California Press.

Newton, Michael, et al (1997). In Touch with a New World: Celebrating Adult Learning at WEA Sydney, State Library of NSW, Mitchell Library.

Reitter, Paul and Chad Wellmon (2021). Permanent Crisis: The Humanities in a Disenchanted Age, The University of Chicago Press

Roberts, Jon H. and James Turner (2000). The Sacred and the Secular University, with an Introduction by John F. Wilson. Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN: 0-6910-1556-2

Sandel, Michael (2020). The Tyranny of Merit: What’s Become of the Common Good? Penguin Random House

Teese, Richard (2000). Academic Success and Social Power: Examinations and Inequality, Melbourne University Press

Willetts, David (2017). A University Education, Oxford University Press

William Clark (2006). Academic Charisma and the Origins of the Research University, University of Chicago Press

University Campus Education Knowledge School Concept

Image: Photo 75687496 / Community Education © Rawpixelimages | Dreamstime.com

Economics of Voluntary-Professional Endeavours in Local History

Economics of Voluntary-Professional Endeavours in Local History

Original Article: Economics of Voluntary-Professional Endeavours in Local History
By Neville Buch
Disclaimer: The views expressed herein are solely those of the author and do not claim to represent the Professional Historians Association.
The economy, or more precisely, economic value, works differently among members of the Professional Historians Association.  Those members who are academics are paid by universities primarily to teach and to gain future research funding by delivering research outputs, mainly publications which will count in Excellence in Research for Australia (ERA) evaluations.  Actually producing history professionally is a by-product in this particular facet of the economy.  Other members are employees of government entities. As public servants, they may have the role of historians but they must perform dissimilar bureaucratic duties for which they are also paid to do.  A few members are consultants in the employ of private companies, and others are freelance consultants.  These members are paid to complete historical projects but are subject to the demands of the market, and many times the market doesn’t want or offer terribly much.
Be it as it may, many members are often engaged with local history organisations. Whether as academics, public servants, consultants, we work alongside volunteers, writing and researching local history, and a recent enquiry has got me thinking on the larger issue of the economics of our combined voluntary-professional endeavours in the local history industry; not only for my purposes as a professional historian, but in fairness to what membership in a local history association is worth for everyone involved.
I had a call from a gentleman as a contact point for my local history group. It is a story not unfamiliar to our PHA members. He wants to know historical details about his property, a site with connections to the emergence of the suburb in the 1880s.  At one level, the conversation involved many things where I could easily assist as a volunteer in a voluntary local history group. At another level, the conversation was moving in another direction.  In this case the gentleman thought that the local railway station had originally been in a different location to its traditional situation, based on a drawing in the estate advertisement of 1886. I suspected that it was simply a matter of the drawing not being to scale, and crafty estate agents wanted to make the station look closer to hand.  However, without verifying evidence I needed to keep an open mind. Nothing was mentioned in the local history publication.  It was a fairly easy thing for me to take a trip to the Queensland State Archive and search the railway plans for the period, but make no mistake, this is professional work. Should I offer the gentleman what he was expecting – someone to go off and give him an answer free of charge? Who am I doing the work for, for the local history group, for the gentleman, or for my own curiosity?
The difficulty is that local history, as indeed family and institutional history, has become a commodity, as well as retaining a non-commercial value to the community at large. And each local history group is also part of that economy. Even though, it is a non-profit organisation it has to cover the costs of the work that everyone puts in, and it should provide nominal recognition for members’ contributions.  Making history a commodity is nothing new and nor is it necessarily a bad thing.  For decades, local history publishers have been a small cottage industry, and professional historians need to be able to sell their labours at a fair price. This is not new. What has changed is that, with increasing number of providers, particularly online providers, history has become a self-service commodity. Providers charge a membership fee that provides access in which anybody can be a do-it-yourself historian (a “DIY historian”).  Again, this is not necessarily a bad thing. The problem is that it makes it difficult for the professional historian to understand where she or he stands in the new emerging economy.  Is there a role for the professional historian in this open-to-all type of market?
It is troubling for the professional historian, but I believe it is trouble for local history groups, in the mix of voluntary-professional roles, unless there is clarity about the input local history association’s offer to the economy. Too often a member of the public will call and expect information to be freely provided which requires someone to locate the primary source, make a trip to a depositary, and provide an answer in form that often taxes some thought. Someone has to pay in the end. We all end up paying for the services of the libraries and the archives through taxes and rates. We do want members of the local community making enquiries. Local history groups don’t want to discourage that, but there is a cost to each group member and the problem is that the value of that cost diminishes in the wider society because it hasn’t been given sufficient economic value.
The point is that local history groups should not be too easy in dispensing with unpublished research work free of any charge. Many local history groups recoup something from the cost of their publications, and that should apply equally to when private interests require information that is gained from extensive archival work. It is a quiet different matter if it is providing information from easily-accessible sources, and little work is required; a chat on the phone and a quick check online or in at-hand hardcopy publications. To expect additional research work free-of-charge which is requested for private ends, as was the case of my recent enquiry, is the dark-side of voluntarism where ‘professional’ labour is exploited. Certainly there is self-interest for me as the professional historian, but the matter applies to other members in the local history group who often offer other types of professional roles. In my own group there is a professional writer who is well-known for her local history work.  Local history groups can have members who are history teachers and those who are graduates in local history studies or women’s history, and who are not members of the Professional Historian Association. All together, whether a professional historian or not, there are members of a local history group who profess skills, training, and experience which is very expensive in our economy. And unfortunately, the public and the state don’t value that cost.
It seems to me a solution lies in how freely research outcomes are shared. It should be freely shared among members. With the agreement of mutual exchanges, it should be freely shared among other local group memberships within History Queensland. It should be utilised for group publication for a cost where funds go back to the group. And when members of the public make requests for information for private use then research outcomes, beyond what is published, should incur a charge. I am inclined to think that a small percentage of the charge be returned to the researcher(s) involved, but perhaps members feel that their labours are a voluntary contribution to the group. I am happy to leave this last thought as a mooted point.
The challenge, though, is not simply with individuals. Larger institutions can also expect too much of voluntary organisations and provide too little in return. What if schools expect local history groups to provide time and effort in provision for their students’ local history units as part of the new national curriculum? That troubles me if it is simply freely provided, when there are poor funding opportunities available to local history groups. The state benefits, but local history groups are made poorer and are required to provide a service free of charge. It is not simply a matter of monetary exchange. It is that there is no benefit for the local history groups. The students will do their projects, and the local history groups are then forgotten. Nothing has been given back in return. Again, there is the dark side of voluntarism, exploiting professional labour without proper compensation. It would be different if there was some type of exchange in kind, so that there were clear benefits to the local history group to the approximate value of what the school gets in the support for teaching their local history units.
Like the subject of economics itself, it gets complex.  However, there is a need for an agreed understanding, on the part of the local groups, the state, and the general community, that voluntarism can only go so far, and that cost of professional history work, whether accredited or not, still needs to be paid. Otherwise we will all be poorer in the end.
Reproduced from PHA (Qld) e-bulletin 20 May 2012, with kind permission of the PHA (Qld) e-bulletin editor.

Centrism (now called neopopulism): I said it, now the NYT is reporting it May 19, 2024

Centrism (now called neopopulism): I said it, now the NYT is reporting it May 19, 2024

Dear Friends, and I thank Graham Perrett’s office for its recent kind support, and several friends who made sure I have not gone under,

 

I said it, now the NYT  is reporting it May 19, 2024: Gift Article (I paid for it, the least you can do is read)
So, I said it back in March with the emerging American sources on the ground, so why does the Queensland powers-that-be give me the silent treatment when I am on the top of the intellectual “game” in this state? Is it the corruption in the thinking?????????????
For intelligence, see the reference of Henry Reining (1959). Your (I am talking to the uncompassionate and unkind) thinking is so out-of-date, spiralling around in ignorance. See how old some of the references are.
Centrism (now called neopopulism)
 
REFERENCES (TOP SELECTION — WRITERS WHO ARE BETTER THAN THE Stupid (made stupid in arrogance) “SMARTS”)
 
David Leonhardt (2024). A New Centrism Is Rising in Washington, The New York Times, May 19, 2024.
 
Neville Buch (2024). The American-Australian Center-Centre, Dr Neville Buch ABN: 86703686642, March 29, 2024.
 
 
******

Anderson, T. J. (1965). Pressure Groups and Intergovernmental Relations. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 359, 116–126. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1035114

Arrington, T. S. (1975). Some Effects of Political Experience on Issue Consciousness and Issue Partisanship among Tuscon Party Activists. American Journal of Political Science, 19(4), 695–702. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110722

Barnes, S. H., & Pierce, R. (1971). Public Opinion and Political Preferences in France and Italy. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(4), 643–660. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110046

Bell, R. (1969). The Determinants of Psychological Involvement in Politics: A Causal Analysis. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 13(2), 237–253. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110176

Bone, H. A. (1958). Political Parties and Pressure Group Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 319, 73–83. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1032438

Buchanan, W. (1965). Politics and Federalism: Party or Anti-Party? The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 359, 107–115. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1035113

Buchanan, W. (1962). Federal Aid to Education on the Conservative-Liberal Scale. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 344, 55–64. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033075

Buck, J. V. (1972). Presidential Coattails and Congressional Loyalty. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(3), 460–472. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110093

Charlesworth, J. C. (1967). National Character in the Perspective of Political Science. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 370, 23–29. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1038047

Clausen, A. R. (1972). State Party Influence on Congressional Policy Decision. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(1), 77–101. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110411

Cornwell, E. E. (1964). Bosses, Machines, and Ethnic Groups. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 27–39. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036061

Daalder, H., & Irwin, G. A. (1974). Interests and Institutions in the Netherlands: An Assessment by the People and by Parliament. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 413, 58–71. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1040567

Dobson, D., & Meeter, D. A. (1974). Alternative Markov Models for Describing Change in Party Identification. American Journal of Political Science, 18(3), 487–500. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110627

Ebersole, L. (1960). Religion and Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 332, 101–111. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033792

Grant, L. V. (1973). Specialization as a Strategy in Legislative Decision-Making. American Journal of Political Science, 17(1), 123–147. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110477

Ginsberg, B. (1972). Critical Elections and the Substance of Party Conflict: 1844-1968. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(4), 603–625. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110379

Greenstein, F. I. (1964). The Changing Pattern of Urban Party Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 1–13. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036059

Gump, W. R. (1971). The Functions of Patronage in American Party Politics: An Empirical Reappraisal. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(1), 87–107. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110251

Jackson, J. E. (1975). Issues, Party Choices, and Presidential Votes. American Journal of Political Science, 19(2), 161–185. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110431

Jones, C. O. (1974). Between Party Battalions and Committee Suzerainty. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 411, 158–168. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1041009

Hinckley, B. (1972). Coalitions in Congress: Size and Ideological Distance. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 16(2), 197–207. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110055

Hinderaker, I. (1966). Political Party Officials: Responsiveness to the Public. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 363, 28–35. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036465

Kammerer, G. M., & DeGrove, J. M. (1964). Urban Leadership during Change. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 95–106. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036067

Koeppen, S. R. (1969). The Republican Radical Right. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 382, 73–82. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1037116

Kornberg, A., Smith, J., Clarke, M.-J., & Clarke, H. D. (1973). Participation in Local Party Organizations in the United States and Canada. American Journal of Political Science, 17(1), 23–47. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110473

Knoke, D. (1974). Religion, Stratification and Politics: American in the 1960s. American Journal of Political Science, 18(2), 331–345. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110705

Lenhart, R. F., & Schriftgiesser, K. (1958). Management in Politics. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 319, 32–40. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1032434

Lowenthal, R. (1963). Factors of Unity and Factors of Conflict. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 349, 106–116. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1035701

Ordeshook, P. C. (1970). Extensions to a Model of the Electoral Process and Implications for the Theory of Responsible Parties. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 14(1), 43–70. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110392

Orlans, H. (1971). The Political Uses of Social Research. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 394, 28–35. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1039287

Pempel, T. J. (1974). The Bureaucratization of Policymaking in Postwar Japan. American Journal of Political Science, 18(4), 647–664. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110551

Pierce, J. C. (1970). Party Identification and the Changing Role of Ideology in American Politics. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 14(1), 25–42. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110391

Pomper, G. (1967). “If Elected, I Promise”: American Party Platforms. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 11(3), 318–352. https://doi.org/10.2307/2108616

Przeworski, A., & Sprague, J. (1971). Concepts in Search of Explicit Formulation: A Study in Measurement. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 15(2), 183–218. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110270

Riedel, J. A. (1964). Boss and Faction. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 353, 14–26. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036060

Reining, H. (1959). The Government Contract as an Administrative Device. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 323, 68–79. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033527

Shannon, J. B. (1962). Conservatism. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 344, 13–24. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1033071

Silvert, K. H. (1965). Parties and the Masses. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 358, 101–108. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036360

Stillman, E. O. (1958). The Beginning of the “Thaw,” 1953-1955. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 317, 12–21. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1031073

Weeks, K. M. (1970). Members of Parliament and the New Zealand Ombudsman System. Midwest Journal of Political Science, 14(4), 673–686. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110359

Wellhofer, E. S. (1974). Political Parties as “Communities of Fate”: Tests with Argentine Party Elites. American Journal of Political Science, 18(2), 347–363. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110706

Wellhofer, E. S., & Hennessey, T. M. (1974). Political Party Development: Institutionalization, Leadership Recruitment, and Behavior. American Journal of Political Science, 18(1), 135–165. https://doi.org/10.2307/2110658

Wilcox, W. (1965). Politicians, Bureaucrats, and Development in India. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science, 358, 114–122. http://www.jstor.org/stable/1036362

Featured Image: American-Australian-Intellectual-Cultural-Relations.png
Micro and Macro, Thin and Thick: Do we really understand our decision making?

Micro and Macro, Thin and Thick: Do we really understand our decision making?

A significant slice on the global history of sociology, philosophy, and historiography has been around discussions of Micro and Macro scopings, and Thin and Thick concepts, with the best scholars examining what Randall Collins calls, “interaction ritual” (IR). The sociological concept was first introduced in Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-Face Behavior, a 1967 book by Erving Goffman. The concepts are slightly different between Collins and Goffman but the concepts are mutually supportive. In the first essay, “On Face-work”, Goffman discusses the concept of face, which is the positive self-image a person holds when interacting with others, and Goffman believes that face “as a sociological construct of interaction is neither inherent in nor a permanent aspect of the person”. Reinhard Bendix‘s work State and Society (1973) enabled Collins to later combine this theory with Erving Goffman’s microsociology, which resulted in Collins’ publication Conflict Sociology in 1975 and later, Interaction Ritual Chains in 2004. Goffman was also one of Collins’ professors during his time at Berkeley. Collins’ identifies interaction ritual more in terms of cognition links in schools of thought.

 

 

 

It was Randall Collins’s book, The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change (1998), which taught me the problems of schooling, along with the paradigmatic criticism of Ivan Illich (via Michael Macklin). As Douglas Goodman (2001), as a critic of Collins, wrote:

 

 

 

Randall Collins has always been interested in what he calls a “non-obvious” sociology (1982). A nonobvious sociology is one that reveals the hidden processes behind what is taken for granted and that demonstrates why the obvious questions are not necessarily the most central ones. [page 92]

Sociologies of other disciplines tend to strike readers, especially those in the targeted field, as attempts to expand the jurisdiction of sociology and to fulfill Comte’s dream of making sociology the ultimate explanatory foundation for all intellectual pursuits. Although we see some of this in Collins, his primary goal in this latest work is not to sociologically explain away philosophical truths. Instead Collins intends to use the history of philosophy to test his ideas about the relationship between concrete human interactions and social structures-that is, the relation between what have come to be called the micro and the macro. [page 92]

Whether the details of the work are ultimately convincing is beyond the scope of this article, but no reader can be unimpressed by the geographic breadth and depth of Collins’s attempt. Following the overview of the theory is a discussion both of what I find unconvincing in the micro theory and also of what I feel are Collins’s new contributions to the sociology of knowledge. Finally, I will suggest what sociology of knowledge might say about sociological theory itself [page 93; my emphasis on the author’s thinking]

Collins’s view of the micro-macro relation is inspired by the empirical achievements such microsociological approaches as ethnomethodology and conversational analysis. These microsociologies do not wholly reject macrosociological concepts, but they improve on their explanations by reconstituting macroconcepts on radically empirical foundations. Whether structures change or persist depends entirely upon whether lying microbehaviors change or persist (Collin 1981: 989). Collins often describes structures as simple aggregates of microevents and has suggested a rather dubious sampling strategy that would ignore all traditional macrosociological variables (Collins 1981:988). [page 94]

Collins’s sociology combines a micro theory of emotional solidarity with a macro theory based on conflict. Collins believes that the same processes that produce solidarity on the micro level produce conflict on the macro. The cultural capital, emotional energy, and group solidarities produced in IRs [interaction rituals] allow individuals to dominate hierarchies and encourage groups to engage in concerted conflict. IRs are both a site where domination is practiced and a supplier of the major weapons used in social conflict. [page 95]

[Goodman’s key criticism] his theory lacks the prime advantage that Collins sees in a micro approach, its openness to empirical testing. Increases in emotional energy are no more observable than any of the macrostructures that Collins labels as nonempirical abstractions. In an articles Collins (1990b:50) admits as much. “My argument, that EE [emotional energy] declines over a series of interaction rituals depending upon the ups and experiences of power and status, is inferential. There is little direct evidence for it.” [page 97]

 

 

 

Goodman’s criticism of Collins’ paradigm fails because it is on any reasonable reading a non-acceptance of nonempirical abstractions, and, as such, it is prejudice, a rationally-argued anti-intellectualism among academics. Philosophical principles (including ethics) are generally nonempirical abstractions; even consequentialist theories has to start in the metaphysics to prioritise natural values. A non-acceptance of nonempirical abstractions blanketly rejects all other theory for theoretical pragmaticism; that is, trapped and stuck thinking.

 

 

 

Nevertheless, as cited by Goodman it can be seen what is valuable. So, Collins does “not to sociologically explain away philosophical truths. Instead Collins intends to use the history of philosophy to test his ideas about the relationship between concrete human interactions and social structures-that is, the relation between what have come to be called the micro and the macro.” Amongst the preservation of that methodology of ‘philosophical truths’ are the meta-reflective conceptions of ‘thin concepts’ and ‘thick concepts’. The terms come from the fields of metaphilosophy and ethics, metaethics:

 

 

 

Yet another way of categorizing metaethical theories is to distinguish between centralist and non-centralist moral theories. The debate between centralism and non-centralism revolves around the relationship between the so-called “thin” and “thick” concepts of morality: thin moral concepts are those such as good, bad, right, and wrong; thick moral concepts are those such as courageous, inequitable, just, or dishonest. While both sides agree that the thin concepts are more general and the thick more specific, centralists hold that the thin concepts are antecedent to the thick ones and that the latter are therefore dependent on the former. That is, centralists argue that one must understand words like “right” and “ought” before understanding words like “just” and “unkind.” Non-centralism rejects this view, holding that thin and thick concepts are on par with one another and even that the thick concepts are a sufficient starting point for understanding the thin ones. (Wikipedia).

 

 

 
 

A number of other psychological theories may also shed light on behaviour in the political context of avoiding understanding human factors, such as cost-benefit analysis, and free-choice paradigm. What strikes me in the debates are several observations:

 

 

 

  • People actively avoid situations and information likely to increase cognitive dissonance – the discomfort from holding contradictory beliefs, ideas, or values, or dealing with new information that conflicts with existing beliefs, ideas, or values.
  • People do not think much about their attitudes, let alone whether they are in conflict. They can come to conclusions as observers without much (or no) emotional or intellectual (cognitive) reflection.

 

 

 

Nevertheless, in spite of an over-emphasis in rational process or agency, there are basic elements in reasoning and choice which ought not to be ignored. Ideas on action and motivation may also provide some illumination. We continue to make ethical judgements. We can identify a person’s motivation as malice, intellectual laziness, or just plain ignorance. These are what Bernard Williams called thick concepts – the way we, at the same time, combine our valuation and facts of the matter in language. We see it in others because we think and feel in the same way. It is an inescapable part of our socialization. It is also a fact about how the brain is “wired”. The big mistake of the ancients, and which we continue in modernity, is to emphasize the difference between emotion and reason.

 

 

 

In current discussions today on democracy, the biggest threat is the thin concept of “We the People”, and the solution is the thick concept of “We the Persons”. If you ask the question, who are people it is easy to see it is a thin concept, as the explanation goes not further than a category. If you ask the question, who are the persons it is easy to see it is a thick concept, since the question leads into the scholarship of personalism. What we get today are the thin concepts of the political rhetoric, signs without substance but which infer hidden or undisclosed beliefs. The advantage of thick concepts is that this political rhetoric has greater clarity. Now, as I argued in my past essay, The Level Playing Field:

 

 

 

Every idea, word, term has a fit, in that we can measure some meaningful signal from when a person uses an idea, word, or term to explain their own beliefs. It has become fashionable in all quarters to nastily dismiss a proposition where someone is attempting to explain an idea, word, or term, and this is to deny any meaningful content in the thinking offer. This is absolute cynicism and should not be accepted in society, but provided as the meaning of a moronic thinking, and not to be hypocritical, each must admit that, to some measure, it is performed by each person sometime past. It is an emotional reaction of human development and society agrees it is a stage of immaturity; although most of us keep falling intermittently for this emotional trap.

 

 

 

All of the terms and concepts in this article has a fit to, not one, but to several overlapping schemas. Furthermore, there are many more sociological terms and concepts which can also be identified (many thanks to Neil Peach for the list; Szakolczai 2023):

 

 

 

  • Liminality: 1. occupying a position at, or on both sides of, a boundary or threshold. 2. relating to a transitional or initial stage of a process. (Oxford)
  • Trickster: a person who cheats or deceives people. (Oxford)
  • Imitation: 1. the action of using someone or something as a model. 2. a thing intended to simulate or copy something else. (Oxford)
  • Schismogensis: Schismogenesis is a term in anthropology that describes the formation of social divisions and differentiation. Literally meaning “creation of division”, the term derives from the Greek words ÏƒÏ‡ÎŻÏƒÎŒÎ±Â skhisma “cleft” (borrowed into English as schism, “division into opposing factions”), and ÎłÎ­ÎœÎ”ÏƒÎčς genesis “generation, creation” (deriving in turn from gignesthai “be born or produced, creation, a coming into being”). The term was introduced by anthropologist Gregory Bateson and has been applied to various fields. (Wikipedia)
  • (Total) Participation: the action of taking part in something. (Oxford)

 

 

 

Taken all together, what this article is arguing, as a summative statement, is that true learning are three metaethical concepts, which align together, and with all other terms and concepts mentioned in the article:

 

 

 

  • (true) Open Access: the unrestricted right or opportunity to use or benefit from something, in particular academic writing or research. (Oxford)
  • Open Participation: Open Participation. Means that anyone may attend a Committee meeting and have the opportunity to offer an opinion on the subject of the meeting, or otherwise participate as a member of the advisory group. (Law Insider)
  • Open and Level Playing Field: A level playing field is simply a fair way to compare or judge two things. (Britannica)

 

 

 

The full argument is a forthcoming essay. But the ‘thisness,’ here (Haecceity), is a start to a critical thinking conversation.

 

 

 

BIBLIOGRAPHY

 

Berlin, Isaiah (with Bernard Williams) ‘Pluralism and Liberalism: A Reply’ (to George Crowder, ‘Pluralism and Liberalism’, Political Studies 42 (1994), 293–303), Political Studies 42 (1994), 306–9
Berlin, Isaiah (1958). Two Concepts of Liberty, Lecture, at the University of Oxford on 31 October 1958.

Collins, Randall (1998). The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change, Harvard Unversity Press.
Collins, Randall (1999). Macrohistory : essays in sociology of the long run. Stanford University Press, Stanford, Calif
Collins, Randall (2005). Interaction ritual chains. Princeton University Press, Princeton, N.J. ; Oxford
Collins, Randall (2008). Violence A Micro-sociological Theory, Princeton University Press
Collins, Randall (2019). The Credential Society: An Historical Sociology of Education and Stratification, Columbia University Press.

Goodman, Douglas (2001). What Collins’s The Sociology of Philosophies Says about Sociological Theory. Sociological Theory (American Sociological Association), Vol. 19, No. 1 (Mar., 2001), pp. 92-101.

Macklin, Michael (1972). To Deschool Society, Cold Comfort, December 1972.
Macklin, Michael (1975).  Those Misconceptions are not Illich’s, Educational Theory, 25 (3), 323-329
Macklin, Michael (1976). When Schools are Gone: A Projection of the Thought of Ivan Illich, St. Lucia: University of Queensland Press.
Macklin, Michael (1986). Education in and for a Multicultural Australia, Australian Teachers Federation Conference, Sydney, October 1986.

Peach, Neil (2005). Academic planning and strategic planning: strangers in the night or potent weapons for strategic competitive advantage?Academia.edu .

Peach, Neil (2009). Planning for a sustainable academic future. Academia. edu .

Peach, Neil (2019). Individualised learning approach (the three ‘p’s) for a small to medium enterprise through work based learning, Academia.edu .

Szakolczai, Arpad (2023). Political Anthropology as Method. Routledge (pages 195 – 204).

Williams, Bernard (1981). Moral Luck, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, Bernard (1985). Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy, London: Fontana.
Williams, Bernard (1995). Making Sense of Humanity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, Bernard (1995). World, Mind, and Ethics: Essays on the ethical philosophy of Bernard Williams, J.E.J.Altham and Ross Harrison (eds.), with “Replies” by Bernard Williams. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Williams, Bernard (2002). Why Philosophy Needs History, London Review of Books, October 17, 7–9.
Williams, Bernard (2002): Truth and Truthfulness: An Essay in Genealogy, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Williams, Bernard (2005). Philosophy as a Humanistic Discipline, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Williams, Bernard (2005). The Sense of the Past: Essays on the History of Philosophy, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
Williams, Bernard, ‘Berlin, Isaiah (1909–97)’, in Routledge Encyclopaedia of Philosophy (London and New York, 1998: Routledge), vol. 1, 750–3

 

 

 

Featured Image: Get off the public path. Choose an alternative way. Thinking outside the box. Atypical leadership thinking qualities. Conformism denial. Detachment. Search for new opportunities. Over the border.  Photo 247705837 | Public Thinking © Andrii Yalanskyi | Dreamstime.com

 

 

 

 

Being Alone and Urban Space: 4 Conferences, 2 Weeks, 2 Cities

Being Alone and Urban Space: 4 Conferences, 2 Weeks, 2 Cities

 

 

I am alone, not like this blank page to which I start to write. We are thrown into a world (Heidegger).

 

 

I woke up slowly this morning. I slept in. Each morning since 17 December 2016, I awake with a sense of disorientation, and in loss and grief. I am alone.

 

 

Isolation is different from person to person, and what is common is the experience is only to a smaller group of persons. I am a widower who lost the love of his life at her young age of 55 years. The context immediately places the loss and grief in a certain way. My wife was “sick” with a brain cancer and I was her carer for seven years. It has been seven years since Ruth died. While Ruth lived with the ‘death sentence’, she was determined to live life as best she could on her own terms. Her work career had just started after many years of study and parttime work, and then it was turned around. She took on a retired life in those seven years, that meant that I did not, or could not, engage as much as, in retrospect I wish I had. Worse, being close to her elderly mother it seemed to me that she became an elderly companion to her mother, well-aged beyond her actual years. It seemed I suddenly became married to a much older woman who I was caring for. It created something of a barrier for myself and my two daughters who were frustrated that their mother had prematurely loss her vigour. We had just hit on a solution to which Ruth agreed – that she would return to her social work studies – when the tumour returned, and her hope for an M.A. in social work was abandoned. Then the laborious and dark year of 2016, of initial vain hope, heartbreak, and isolation. Ruth died alone. Ruth did not die alone. It is a paradox. No one could really be there for Ruth as she was in the dying stages of six months. She was alone, slipping away from us. Nevertheless, we – I, family, friends – were in her presence to the end. I felt the distancing from the love of my heart. The love remained, but it became distant, as Ruth slipped into long periods of sleep, and there was less engagement to express love: too few hugs, too few words. The barrier was also self-preservation in the shock of losing not only a loved one, but my life, my life with Ruth. Ruth was alone. I was alone.

 

 

Writing these words on the remaining blank page, tears are running down my face after seven years.

 

 

Being alone, however, in the last seven years has another dimension.

 

 

I have just completed four conferences in two weeks, as I write these words on a Sunday morning and afternoon from Room 603 at the Marriot in Auckland. It is a sign of an achievement in my new life, and yet I feel very much alone, a different kind of aloneness. In my life with Ruth, we had compromised much in our work careers, mutually. Both of us lost those opportunities of advancing in our career. Both of us had hopes for advancement, but I was particularly ambitious to be the teacher and researcher at the head podium of the conference.  But to achieve such ambitious status, I would have to have had the paid position in the university, but much more, I would have had to put in the required hours away from the family. This was not possible in life with Ruth, and it was part of our mutual compromise.

 

 

Now in the absence of Ruth, the opportunities have come too late. For the whole of my life, with or without Ruth, it was always too late: too late to make my own mark in the cognitive revolution of the 1960s and 1970s, being too young. Too late as an undergraduate student, moving on into my late 20s. Too late as a doctoral student in my early 30s, which meant too late in my initial career as a higher education researcher in my late 30s. Very few excelling scholars can get ahead of the crowd and stake the direction of the mass culture. Working in a university office, you are in the midst of the madness with temporary and insignificant tasks. It was only in the years after I left the Office of Vice-Chancellor, University of Melbourne, that it made any sense what was happening. It is the concept of historical distancing. Hegel’s ancient owl. Now, I can write the exceptionally important papers for the intellectual histories of higher learning, but, tragically, my colleagues have moved onto other important and critical matters; so, who cares what a 62-year-old has to say, “isn’t he retired.” I am alone.

 

 

Furthermore,  what I have to say is incredibly discomforting to my university colleagues who remain in the madness. I am saying, for the communities I work for, is that academics across the fields, are only “shifting the deckchairs” of higher learning, and higher learning still remains as aloof to the lebenphilosophie of public space communities. There are too few scholars, who are actually inside the public space communities, translating the vast literature of higher learning, and we are the ones with the crushed university ambitions. And we are also the ones without payment for our work since voluntary work is so undervalued in our society. Academics talk about doing voluntary work for the scholarly societies but they forget that they do so from a wage that is paid by the university. I am alone.

 

 

Ambition is thawed away, not merely in the closed-off opportunity. One is self-aware of the shortfall of living one’s life. For me, it was always languages. It was something in my childhood disposition, that growing up I could never distinguish well, audiologically, in pronunciation and tone. Tone also meant that I could express anger without understanding the tone heard as aggression. If I felt the aggression in myself, I had translate it as frustration at the lack of attention I felt I was receiving. Life had meant I knew humility, but the lack of attention was interpreted in my historian’s frame: I was continually misunderstood due to wilful historical forgetfulness. Academics caught up in rabbit holes of specialisation just did not want to know, and why should they care? I was alone.

 

 

I must admit to the marginality of attending and participating in the four conferences, and that I was not alone. It is a similar paradox of the life with Ruth, mentioned above. Academics feel that their position is at the margins. Everyone in public space communities feel at the margins. It is a strange life-experience of being alone, and very much not alone. So, to get academic attention, what does the literature says on being alone?

 

 

Most the literature relates dispassionate and clinical studies, as expected, but there were nine works directly related to my argument on being alone (Hughes and Gove 1981; Ranta, Rita, Lindstrom 1993; Stack 1998; Coleman 2009; Gaymu, Springer, and Stringer 2012; Demey, Berrington, Evandrou, and Falkingham 2014; Holt-Lunstad, Smith, Baker, Harris, and Stephenson 2015; Frank, Froese, Hof, Scheffold, Schreyer, Zeller, and Rödder, 2017; Wilkinson, Tomlinson, and Gardiner 2017).

 

 

As to the dispassionate and clinical studies, the literature mostly focuses on the conditions of older persons in Asian cultures and philosophies (Raymo 2015; Kim 2015; Min-Ah Lee 2016), with two European or western paralleled concern (Kemp and Acheson 1989; de Jong, Dykstra, Schenk 2012). Another area of clinical concern was young persons living alone in one-person households (Cheung and Yeung 2015, 2021);

 

 

  • Raymo (2015) uses Japanese census data to evaluate how much of the growth in one-person households at ages 20–39 between 1985 and 2010 is explained by change in marital behaviour and how much is explained by other factors. The analyses indicate that marital behaviour had correlated with certain increase in one-person households for men and three-fourths of the increase for women. That is interesting but that does not go anywhere in understanding the film, Lost in Translation. Surprise, surprise, the second set of analyses indicated that those living alone are significantly less happy than those living with others.

 

 

  • Kim (2015) has a more honest appraisal from the data, concluding it is not clear whether public transfers for the elderly will increase or decrease their independent living. Furthermore, as is supported in much intergenerational studies of the last 60 years, multigenerational co-residence is prevalent and norms and preferences for that form of living arrangement remain strong. I do love my daughters living at home when they do;

 

 

  • Min-Ah Lee (2016) used data from the four waves of the Korean Longitudinal Study of Ageing (KLoSA) over a period of six years, discrete time event history analyses were conducted to analyse the determinants of the transition to living alone for older Koreans. What was found was that home ownership and higher household income at a previous wave were negatively associated with the transition to living alone in general, whereas prior depressive symptoms were positively associated with the transition to living alone for older Koreans. It is certainly counter-intuitive. To say, physical health conditions did not have significant effects on the transition to living alone is aggressively opposite of the lebenphilosophie, as the global population finds it. Although Min-Ah Lee does conclude that the transition to living alone in disadvantaged older adults may amplify the harmful effects of living alone on their well-being in the long run, his approach to the data is problematic. Statistics is always subject to false reading from what the expectations of the participants have in what should be reported;

 

 

  • In 1989 Kemp and Acheson did better work in tying the experience of being alone to the care of community. They sampled 2,000 elderly people from 20 general practitioner practices in the East Anglia area. Those living alone exhibit a higher level of independence than those living with others, but nearly a quarter of those aged 75 and over living alone did rely on someone else entirely for specific tasks;

 

 

  • de Jong et al (2012) used data from the Generations and Gender Surveys of three countries in Eastern Europe and two countries in Western Europe. Latent Class Analyses was applied to develop intergenerational support types for (a) co-residing respondents in Eastern Europe, (b) respondents in independent households in Eastern Europe, and (c) respondents in independent households in Western Europe, respectively. On this basis, a six-way typology was produced. It is fascinating reading, but, again, the lebenphilosophie is simply not there;

 

 

  • In Cheung and Yeung’s (2015, 2021) major paper, they drew data (from previous studies to the meta-data) from a subsample of young adults (aged between 20 and 35) from China 1% Population Sample Survey 2005 (ni = 582,139; nj = 345). They concluded that young adults living in one-person households (OPHs) had increased remarkably worldwide. This analysis is informative to both living alone and having to migrate to live alone. A second paper was published, but it appears almost the same as the earlier study.

 

 

There is an academic game-playing which distorts the intelligence in the academic research and findings, and particularly, missed lebenphilosophie.

 

 

As to the actually academic articles writing on the being alone:

 

 

  1. In 1981 Hughes and Gove immediately went to the much better research, and providing an examination of the effects of living alone on mental health, mental well-being, and maladaptive behaviours. Their work reflects the general ethos of the 1980s, in that there was much more concern among academics for compatibilist philosophy and horizon worldviews. The work in academy, in later decades, trended the statistical analysis without the quality consideration of the philosophic concepts in the works. Hughes and Gove showed there is no evidence that persons who live alone are selected into supported living arrangement because of preexisting psychological problems, noxious personality characteristics, or incompetent socioeconomic behaviour, and that, contrary to structural functionalism or symbolic interactionism, unmarried persons who live alone are in no worse, and on some indicators are in better, mental health than unmarried persons who live with others. The big gap in their work is the absence of references to widows and widowers. Most academics cannot deal with loss and grief until it becomes their own lebenphilosophie;

 

 

  1. In 1993 Ranta et al produced a very bland paper, which reported to speak to “Competition Versus Cooperation”, Admittedly it was an anthropological paper about food foraging alone and in groups. They argued that the option of foraging alone may easily be a better strategy than that of a low-ranking individual foraging in a group. However, as a generic argument, it is bullshit. As interdisciplinary scholars are aware, the competitive and Darwinian social models does not work for the benefit of the individual nor the group. The argument of Ranta et al is so obviously agenda-ed, as all academic works are. There is no evidence that the lebenphilosophie of a low-ranking individual is better without the deep group interaction and worldview;

 

 

  1. In 1998 Stack pointed out that previous research on loneliness had often neglected the role of marriage and family ties, comparative analysis, and cohabitation. Using the data from 17 nations in the World Values Survey, they concluded (1) marriage is associated with substantially less loneliness, but parenthood is not, (2) being married was considerably more predictive of loneliness than cohabitation, indicating that companionship alone does not account for the protective nature of marriage, (3) both marriage and parental status were associated with lower levels of loneliness among men than women, (4) marriage is associated with decreased loneliness independent of two intervening processes: marriage’s association with both health and financial satisfaction, (5) the strength of the marriage-loneliness relationship is constant across 16 of the 17 nations. Again, there is not the consideration of the end of marriage through experience of ‘pre-mature’ death;

 

 

  1. In the new century Coleman (2009) went to the characteristic urban experience of solitude and its challenges to traditional anthropological theories of urban life. It challenged theoretical perspectives with ethnographic cases of gay identities and ‘being alone together,’ drawn from fieldwork in New Delhi, India. Personally, in the different context of heterosexuality, I found Colman’s heuristic concept of ‘social solitude’, in contrast to ‘solidarity’, and his examination of the political and philosophical consequences of focusing on solitude as an urban way of life and an expression of sexuality, an epistemic fit. Coleman drew his informative model from a reading of Deleuze;

 

 

  1. Gaymu et al (2012), finally, lands on the lebenphilosophie directly. They looked at the influence of living conditions on the life satisfaction of men and women over 60 years of age in ten European countries using data from the European survey SHARE 2004 (wave 1). The features that they examine are the same of my lebenphilosophie argument: income levels, homeownership, and the relationship between family roles and economic status;

 

 

  1. Demey et al (2014) examined studies which found that the duration since a union dissolution and the number of union dissolutions are associated with psychological well-being. Again, the lebenphilosophie of widows and widowers are not relevant – not a matter of ‘union dissolution’ in the full semantics of the experience;

 

 

  1. Holt-Lunstad et al (2015) comes closer with an examination of actual and perceived social isolation in that both are associated with increased risk for early mortality. They conducted a literature search of studies (January 1980 to February 2014) using MEDLINE, CINAHL, PsycINFO, Social Work Abstracts, and Google Scholar. Again, the interdisciplinary scholarship shows that there is something is wrong, when concluding no differences between measures of objective and subjective social isolation. Their approach was admittedly, marginally, to the compatibilism side, and they did say, “the influence of both objective and subjective social isolation on risk for mortality is comparable with well-established risk factors for mortality”, but that overlooks many object-subject lessons in the interdisciplinary knowledge;

 

 

  1. Frank et al (2017) go directly to my main point here: “The ability to conduct interdisciplinary research is crucial to address complex real-world problems that require the collaboration of different scientific fields, with global warming being a case in point.” Their classroom experiment reminds me of David Kayrouz’s presentation at the PESA conference on knowing and knowledge (images of Kayrouz’s models in the photo album);

 

 

  1. Wilkinson et al (2017), finally, goes to my sorrowful-happy reflections of my life with Ruth, with their examination of the dominant understanding of work–life balance or conflict as primarily a ‘work–family’ issue by exploring the experiences of managers and professionals who live alone and do not have children – a group of employees traditionally overlooked in work–life policy and research but, significantly, a group on the rise within the working age population. Of course, Ruth and I had two wonderful children, but Wilkinson et al’s analysis does not go to lebenphilosophie of widows and widowers, with or without children.

 

 

 

The always continuing conclusions

 

 

I have spent this Sunday writing this “academic article”, without family close-by, and without a loving partner, has provided the insight to what being alone is about. As an interdisciplinary scholar, outside the university, and for the public square community, I am alone. So much for academic collegialism! Still, I am supported in kindness by individual academics and former academics. And I thank them dearly, for when I do not feel alone.

 

 

REFERENCES

Cheung, A. K.-L., & Yeung, W.-J. J. (2021). Socioeconomic development and young adults’ propensity of living in one-person households: Compositional and contextual effects. Demographic Research, 44, 277–306. https://www.jstor.org/stable/27032913

Coleman, L. (2009). Being Alone Together: From Solidarity to Solitude in Urban Anthropology. Anthropological Quarterly, 82(3), 755–777. http://www.jstor.org/stable/20638659

de Jong Gierveld, J., Dykstra, P. A., & Schenk, N. (2012). Living arrangements, intergenerational support types and older adult loneliness in Eastern and Western Europe. Demographic Research, 27, 167–200. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26349921

Demey, D., Berrington, A., Evandrou, M., & Falkingham, J. (2014). Living alone and psychological well-being in mid-life: does partnership history matter? Journal of Epidemiology and Community Health (1979-), 68(5), 403–410. http://www.jstor.org/stable/43281754

Frank, A. M., Froese, R., Hof, B. C., Scheffold, M. I. E., Schreyer, F., Zeller, M., & Rödder, S. (2017). Riding alone on the elevator: A class experiment in interdisciplinary education. Learning and Teaching: The International Journal of Higher Education in the Social Sciences, 10(3), 1–19. https://www.jstor.org/stable/48561574

Gaymu, J., Springer, S., & Stringer, L. (2012). How does Living Alone or with a Partner Influence Life Satisfaction among Older Men and Women in Europe? Population (English Edition, 2002-), 67(1), 43–69. http://www.jstor.org/stable/23358620

Holt-Lunstad, J., Smith, T. B., Baker, M., Harris, T., & Stephenson, D. (2015). Loneliness and Social Isolation as Risk Factors for Mortality: A Meta-Analytic Review. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 10(2), 227–237. http://www.jstor.org/stable/44290063

Hughes, M., & Gove, W. R. (1981). Living Alone, Social Integration, and Mental Health. American Journal of Sociology, 87(1), 48–74. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2778539

Kemp, Frances M., and Roy M. Acheson. “Care in the Community – Elderly People Living Alone at Home.” Community Medicine 11, no. 1 (1989): 21–26. http://www.jstor.org/stable/45156782.

Kim, E. H.-W. (2015). Public transfers and living alone among the elderly: A case study of Korea’s new income support program. Demographic Research, 32, 1383–1408. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26350156

Min-Ah Lee. (2016). Effects of Economic and Health Conditions on the Transition to Living Alone: A Longitudinal Study on Older Koreans. Development and Society, 45(3), 591–617. http://www.jstor.org/stable/deveandsoci.45.3.591

Ranta, E., Rita, H., & Lindstrom, K. (1993). Competition Versus Cooperation: Success of Individuals Foraging Alone and in Groups. The American Naturalist, 142(1), 42–58. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2462633

Raymo, J. M. (2015). Living alone in Japan: Relationships with happiness and health. Demographic Research, 32, 1267–1298. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26350152

Stack, S. (1998). Marriage, Family and Loneliness: A Cross-National Study. Sociological Perspectives, 41(2), 415–432. https://doi.org/10.2307/1389484

Wilkinson, K., Tomlinson, J., & Gardiner, J. (2017). Exploring the work–life challenges and dilemmas faced by managers and professionals who live alone. Work, Employment & Society, 31(4), 640–656. https://www.jstor.org/stable/26500128

Yeung, W.-J. J., & Cheung, A. K.-L. (2015). Living alone: One-person households in Asia. Demographic Research, 32, 1099–1112. http://www.jstor.org/stable/26350146